Classics@15: A Concise Inventory of Greek Etymology

  Levaniouk, Olga, ed. 2017–. “A Concise Inventory of Greek Etymology.” Special issue, Classics@ 15. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.jissue:ClassicsAt.Issue15.A_Concise_Inventory_of_Greek_Etymologies.2017.



Edited by Olga Levaniouk

Foreword

A concise inventory of Greek etymologies (CIGE) is an ongoing publication that will be expanded and revised as time goes on. This project’s goal is to provide access to etymologies that are important for the study of Greek culture and that are often not yet referenced in the conventional dictionaries. CIGE represents an understanding of Greek—and especially Homeric—etymology as part of the formulaic system of early Greek poetry. Poetic function can be of crucial etymological importance, and, conversely, etymology can be essential for understanding poetry, especially when it comes to the Homeric lexicon. This is not because the synchronic meaning of a given word is determined by its etymology, but because traditional cultural systems, such as Homeric poetry, evolve over time and have to be approached not only synchronically but also diachronically. The research of Milman Parry (Collected Papers, 1971) and Albert Lord, as presented in Lord’s monograph The Singer of Tales (1960), proved that Homeric poetry is a system generated by and from oral traditions, which, like other linguistic systems, have building blocks (“words” and “expressions”) and rules or habits for combining them. The building blocks of Homeric poetry are “formulas” on the level of form and “themes” on the level of meaning (Lord 1960:4). Etymological study of Homeric vocabulary cannot be divorced from the analysis of this system. In its formative periods the formulaic system of Homeric poetry was not static but evolving, and the overall etymology of the Homeric lexicon reflects that evolution. Citing the paradoxical pronouncement of Emile Benveniste that the study of the Homeric lexicon is “in its infancy,” dans l’enfance (Benveniste 1969 [II]:58), Leonard Muellner observes that “there are available to us two perspectives and the research methods that flow from them that renew the study of Homer globally: first, the notion that Homeric poetry is the product of a traditional system that functioned to meet the needs of composition in performance, and second, that the rigorous study of the history of the Greek language and of the Indo-European family of languages as a whole is important for Homer because the poetic tradition from which it descends already existed, in form, diction, and even to some extent in function, in Indo-European society.” (Muellner 2005. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn3:hlnc.essay:Muellner.Discovery_Procedures_and_Principles_for_Homeric_Research.2005)
It is the goal of the CIGE to assemble examples illustrating these perspectives and these methods and thereby both to take stock of what has been accomplished so far and also to facilitate future research. Not all etymologies featured in CIGE will have equal temporal depth, and the term “etymology” will be understood broadly as a diachronic study of words that sheds light on their meanings. In order to accomplish this goal, an etymology may be, but does not have to be—and often will not be—reconstructed all the way back to Proto-Indo-European. In fact, in some cases it may involve no comparative reconstruction at all. Such an etymology may be discovered entirely by the study of Homeric poetry as a system.
The main content of CIGE is organized in the mode of a dictionary: each entry appears under a heading or lēmma that indicates the basic word to be analyzed. Each entry contains a reference to a fuller analysis, if available, and identifies the author who suggested or advocates the etymology in question. The editors of the individual entries are identified by name-stamp and date-stamp at the end of each entry. Each editor is the owner of his or her own entry as edited. Some entries are divided into parts, numbered A, B, C, D, etc. Occasionally, there are different editors for different parts, in which case the editors of the individual parts are identified by name-stamp and date-stamp at the end of each part. Different analyses may be featured under the same lemma (with authors and editors indicated) and comments may be added to lemma on an on-going basis.
Under separate headings, CIGE also features a selection of short articles and essays on Greek etymologies, broadly understood.

A Concise Inventory of Greek Etymologies

Ἄδμητος (Ádmētos)
Ádmētos (Ἄδμητος) is the son of Pheres, sovereign of Pherae, a Thessalian kingdom. He is a friend of god Apollo, who once served him as his herdsman for one year and helped him in winning the hand of Alcestis. Furthermore, Apollo grants Ádmētos the privilege to avoid death. However, someone else must die in his place. Alcestis, his wife, chooses to die on his behalf but, as we learn from Euripides’s Alcestis, Heracles manages to bring her back to her husband—on Heracles’s pónos in Euripides’s drama, that is, his wrestling match against Death, see Nagy 1990, ch. 5, §4; 2018, vv. 956–960.
The proper name Ádmētos is a homophone of the adjective ádmētos ‘un-tamed’ (Greek ἄδμητος), which is commonly considered the poetic form for the more common adámatos (Greek ἀδάματος) ‘un-tamed’. Both adámatos and ádmētos display a privative alpha (from Indo-European *n̥-) as their first compound member and a second compound member, which can be traced back to the Indo-European root *demh2- ‘tame’. This root underlies Greek dámnēmi (: δάμνημι), damázō (: δαμάζω) ‘tame, overpower’ as well as a variety of cognate verbs with a meaning ‘tame, overpower’, such as, among others, Vedic dami, Old Norse temjan ‘to tame, overpower’. In the epic corpus, the adjective ádmētos occurs in feminine and applies to:

 

(i) ‘cattle’, with the meaning ‘unbroken’, e.g., βοῦν ἦνιν … ἀδμήτην ‘a yearling heifer … unbroken’ (Iliad 10.293+);
(ii) ‘maiden’, with the meaning ‘unwedded’, e.g., παρθένῳ ἀδμήτῃ ‘to an unwedded virgin’ (Homeric Hymn 5.82+).
The analysis of the poetic phraseology in Greek and in other Indo-European languages suggests that Ádmētos is ‘un-tamed’ because he does not die. In a variety of contexts, dámnēmi and damázō denote ‘to kill’ in Greek:

 

ἐπεὶ δὴ τόνδ’ ἄνδρα θεοὶ δαμάσασθαι ἔδωκαν
“… when the gods gave me this man to tame (: to kill)” (Iliad 22.379)
The syntagma ἄνδρα … δαμάσασθαι ‘to tame … a man’ perfectly matches the compound androdámas (ἀνδροδάμας, Alcman+) ‘man-taming or man-killing’ (Massetti 2019: 19–21). Moreover, the verb occurs in connection with θάνατος ‘death’, cf. Euripides Medea 650 θανάτῳ θανάτῳ … δαμείην “may I be tamed by the death, by the death!” In a later phase of Greek poetic language, the epithet pandamátōr (: πανδαμάτωρ) ‘all-taming’ came to apply to Hades, (Greek Anthology 16.213.4+). The semantic development from ‘tame’ to ‘kill’ is attested in other Indo-European languages as well. For instance, Vedic dami ‘to overpower (in battle), dominate’ partially overlaps Vedic han ‘to smash, kill.’ Hence, the compound dasyuhántama– ‘the super smasher (: han) of the Dasyus’ (Rigveda 8.39.8) semantically equals the collocation adamāyo dásyūm̐r “you tamed (dami) the Dasyus” (Rigveda 6.18.3).
In conclusion, the phraseological analysis reveals that Ádmētos’s destiny lies in his name, since he is one who is ‘un-tamed (by Death)’.
Massetti, L. 2019. Phraseologie und indogermanische Dichtersprache in der Sprache der griechischen Chorlyrik: Pindar und Bakchylides. PhD diss., University of Cologne. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_MassettiL.Phraseologie_und_indogermanische_Dichtersprache.2019.
Nagy, G. 1990. Pindar’s Homer. The Lyric Possession of an Epic Past. Online: http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Pindars_Homer.1990.
Nagy, G. 2018. A sampling of comments on the Herakles of Euripides. https://classical-inquiries.chs.harvard.edu/a-sampling-of-comments-on-the-herakles-of-euripides/. (2018.04.20).
 
Laura Massetti 2018.08.11
Ἀπόλλων (Apóllōn)
The etymology of Apollo’s name, Apóllōn, has defied linguistic reconstruction for a long time. A breakthrough came with a 1975 article by Walter Burkert, where he proposes that the Doric form of the name, Apéllōn, be connected with the noun apéllai, designating a seasonally recurring festival—an assembly or thing, in Germanic terms—of Dorian kinship groups. The linguistic principles underlying Burkert’s proposal have been definitively restated in a posthumously published work by Alfred Heubeck, who shows that the earliest recoverable form of the name is *apelyōn, built on a noun shaped *apelya: thus the meaning would be something like ‘he of the assembly’. A Cypriote by-form of Apollo’s name is Apeílōn (to-i-a-pe-lo-ni = τῶι Ἀπείλωνι), showing the earlier e-vocalism as opposed to the innovative o-vocalism of Apóllōn. Following a suggestion from Leonard Muellner, we can say that the name of Apollo can be connected, with recourse to this Cypriote by-form, to the Homeric noun apeilḗ, meaning ‘promise, boastful promise, threat’, and to the corresponding verb, apeiléō ‘make a promise, boastful promise, threat’. The meaning of these forms apeilḗ and apeiléō is based on the concept of a speech-act, and on the fact that this concept dovetails with the meaning of apéllai, based on an actual context of speech-acts. Such dovetailing helps explain the essence of Apollo, ‘he of the *apelya’, as the god of authoritative speech, the one who presides over all manner of speech-acts, including the realms of songmaking in general and poetry in particular.
The word apeiléō designates the actual performance of a speech-act, a mûthos, while the word teléō, derivative of télos ‘fulfillment’, guarantees that the speech-act is really a speech-act, in that the course of events, which amounts to actions emanating from the speech-act, bears out the speech-act. We may compare the Homeric instances where apeiléō can be translated as ‘vow’ in the context of prayers addressed to gods (Iliad 23.863, 892).
Burkert draws attention to the fact that Apollo is conventionally represented as beardless and unshorn, looking like an éphēbos ‘ephebe’, that is, like a pre-adult male. Unlike human pre-adult males, however, the god Apollo is a permanent ephebe. Unlike human males, he will never take over from his father. The basic ephebism of Apollo can be connected with the semantics of apéllai. As Burkert points out, the feast of the apéllai at Delphi is technically a “Feast of Ephebes.” Moreover, we may consider the wording of the so-called Great Rhetra of Sparta, attributed to Lycurgus the lawgiver: ὥρας ἐξ ὡρᾶν ἀπελλάζειν ‘to hold assemblies [apéllai], season [hōrā] after season [hōrā]’ (Plutarch Lycurgus 6). In this case the theme of seasonality, as conveyed by hōrā ‘season’, can be connected with the celebration of young boys’ coming of age, that is, of human seasonality, on the occasion of the apéllai of Delphi.
Apollo, ‘he of the *apelya’, is the god of authoritative speech, the one who presides over all manner of speech-acts. Apollo is not only the god of speech-acts: he is also the god of poetry and song. The god of eternal promise, of the eternity of potential performance, he is the word waiting to be translated into action.
Nagy, G. 2004. Homer’s Text and Language, Chapter 7: “The Name of Apollo: Etymology and Essence.” Champaign, IL. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Homers_Text_and_Language.2004.
Burkert, W. 1975. “Apollon und Apellai.” Rheinisches Museum 118:1–21.
Heubeck, A. 1987. “Noch Einmal zum Namen des Apollon.” Glotta 65:179–182.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Daniel Miller 2015.12.11 and Olga Levaniouk 2016.01.17
ἀρετή (aretḗ)
The term aretḗ (ἀρετή) is conventionally translated as ‘excellence’ and is first attested in the hexametrical traditional poetry. Here, it applies to both human and non-human qualities, take, for instance, Iliad 15.642–643 παντοίας ἀρετάς, ἠμὲν πόδας ἠδὲ μάχεσθαι || καὶ νόον ἐν πρώτοισι Μυκηναίων ἐτέτυκτο ‘in all kind of aretaĩs (qualities), both in fleetness of foot and in fight, and in mind he was among the first of the men of Mycenae’, and Iliad 23.276 ἴστε γὰρ ὅσσον ἐμοὶ ἀρετῇ περιβάλλετον ἵπποι ‘for you know how far my two horses surpass in excellence’. In parallel, the plural form aretaí (ἀρεταί), which originally meant ‘the aretḗ-deeds’, came to denote ‘achievements’, compare, Pindar Nemean 3.32–33 παλαιαῖσι δ᾿ ἐν ἀρεταῖς γέγαθε Πηλεὺς ἄναξ, ὑπέραλλον αἰχμὰν ταμών ‘in achievements of long ago lord Peleus took delight, after cutting his matchless spear’. Moreover, in philosophical works, aretḗ acquired the semantic nuance of ‘(moral) virtue’, such as in Plato Crito 53c ἢ οὕσπερ ἐνθάδε, ὡς ἡ ἀρετὴ καὶ ἡ δικαιοσύνη πλείστου ἄξιον τοῖς ἀνθρώποις καὶ τὰ νόμιμα καὶ οἱ νόμοι; ‘Or will they be the ones (: arguments) you use here, that goodness and justice are of the highest value to mankind together with institutions and laws?’
The noun aretḗ (ἀρετή) may be traced back to the same root as Greek ararískō (ἀραρίσκω) ‘to fit’, harmózō (ἁρμόζω) ‘to join’ and hárma (ἁρμα) ‘chariot’, or ‘the vehicle, whose parts have been fitted together’ (Prellwitz 1931), as well as Greek ἄριστος ‘the best’ (‘the most fitting one’). Indeed, a gloss by the ancient lexicographer Hesychius reflects a synchronical connection between aretáō (ἀρετάω), a denominative verb based on aretḗ and harmózō: Hesychius α 41 L ἀρέτησαν· ἥρμοσαν ‘arétēsan (they did with aretḗ): they harmonized / they joined together’.
As the Greek words aretḗ, ararískō, harmózō and hárma display an initial alpha, all these terms can be traced back to a Proto-Indoeuropean root *(H)ar- ‘fit, join’, that is to say, a root which can be reconstructed as *h2er- or *h1ar- und underlies Vedic sám aranta ‘join’, Young Avestan arånte ‘fasten’.
Some of the Greek terms belonging to this word family have a non etymological initial aspiration, while others lack it. Specifically, Greek hárma (ἁρμα) retains a regressive non etymological aspiration. It may reflect *(H)ar-s-mn̥-, a derivative from the root enlarged with an complex -sm(e)n-suffix or a *(H)r̥s-mn̥- stem, that is to say, a neutral derivative built on the zero grade of a putative s-stem *(H)ar-o/es-. The aspiration of harmózō (ἁρμόζω) ‘join’ could be explained as secondary as well.
By assuming a root *h1ar-, Greek árnumai (ἁρνυμαι) ‘to win, to struggle to win’ and Cuneiform Luvian ārlanuwa- ‘to make (something) owned (by someone)’ (Melchert 1999:246), as well as the Hittite adverb āra– ‘right’, which show no trace of an initial laryngal two, may be included as further linguistic congeners of Greek aretḗ (ἀρετή). As pointed out by Nagy’s comment on Iliad 18.121 and Odyssey 1.5 (Nagy 2017), the Greek hexametrical poetry árnumai (ἁρνυμαι) is often attested in connection with ‘epic goals’, such as, among others, kléos, kũdos (κλέος, κῦδος) ‘glory’, timḗ (τιμή) ‘honor’, aéthlia (ἀέθλια) ‘prize’, nóstos (νόστος) ‘homecoming’. A semantic development from ‘fit’ (Indo-European *h1ar-) to ‘make something fit to oneself’, that is to say, ‘take, win, gain’ (Greek árnumai, Luvian ārlanuwa-) is easily conceivable and, at any rate, not unparalleled, compare German eignen ‘to fit’, zueigen ‘to take something’.
Greek aretḗ (ἀρετή) can thus reflect *(H)ar-eteh2, a feminine or a collective form of an etó-derivative, which originally meant ‘(what is) good to join / to articulate’ (Vine 1998:61). A nominal derivative with a suffix –etó- exists beside a -tó-formation, *(H)r̥-tó-, underlying Vedic r̥tá- ‘cosmic order, rightness, truth’ and *(H)ar-tó-, reflected by Avestan ašạ- ‘rightness, truth’.
The etymological connection between aretḗ (ἀρετή), r̥tá- and ašạ- is confirmed by a wide set of collocations and associations that the three terms have in common (Massetti [in preparation]). To begin with, Greek aretḗ (ἀρετή) is associated to ‘truth’ (alḗtheia, Greek ἀλήθεια) and ‘justice’ (díkē, δίκη), which are semantic structural components of both Vedic r̥tá- and Avestan ašạ-:

 

ἀρχὰ µεγάλας ἀρετᾶς, ὤνασσ᾽ Ἀλάθεια
Pindar fr. 205
‘Starting point of great aretā́, Queen Truth

 

ἐν δὲ δικαιοσύνῃ συλλήβδην πᾶσ᾿ἀρετή᾿στί

Phocylides fr. 10 West
In the justice there is together every aretḗ
Greek poets and philosophers have sometimes likened positive concepts such as ‘truth’ and ‘justice’ to objects consisting of several parts, which have been fitted together, such as the ‘wheel’ and the ‘chariot’. In Parmenides (1.29 DK), the Truth (alḗtheiē) is said to be eukuklḗs (εὐκυκλὴς) ‘which has a beautiful circle / wheel’, while Simonides (11.12 W) speaks of the ‘chariot of the justice’, hárma díkēs (ἅρμα δίκης). As pointed out by Calvert Watkins (1979), Vedic r̥tá– and Avestan ašạ– are associated with the same images. Vedic r̥tá– occurs in the collocations ‘wheel of the r̥tá-’, Vedic cakrám […] r̥tásya (RV 1.164.11b) and the ‘chariot of the r̥tá-’, Vedic ráthaḥ […] r̥tásya (RV 2.23.3b+). Furthermore, both Vedic r̥tá– and Avestan ašạ– are connected to the Proto-Indoeuropean root *u ̯egh- ‘drive’, as few examples can show: ašạhiiā važdr ə̄ ṇg ‘conveyors of the ašạ-’ (Y. 46.4), ūhyā́the […] r̥tám ‘you have conveyed the r̥tá-’ (RV 4.56.6c). Strikingly, Pindar makes aretḗ the direct object of a verb ‘lead’, Greek elaúnō, which commonly applies to chariots and horses in the epic poetry:

 

ἐλᾷ […] ἀρετὰς ὁ θνατὸς αἰών
Pindar Nemean 3.74–75
‘(Our) mortal life drives a team of four aretaí (virtues)’
The Pindaric image indirectly provides a twofold parallel for the semantic shifts underlying aretā́. The ‘team of four aretaí’ recalls the image of a chariot, which is both the vehicle consisting of many parts, which have been fitted together (hárma), and the means for winning a prize in races (árnumai).
Just as Vedic r̥tá- and Avestan ašạ-, Greek aretḗ is associated with the image of the ‘straight, direct path’:

 

εὐθεῖα δὴ κέλευθος ἀρετὰν ἑλεῖν
Pindar fr. 108a.3
Straight indeed is the path to achieve aretā́’

 

ábhūd u pārám étave
pánthā r̥tásya sādhuyā́

RV 1.46.11ab
‘And the path of truth has come into being to lead right to the far shore’

 

sīṣ̌ā nā̊ aṣ̌ā paϑō   vaŋhə̄uš xvaētəṇg manaŋhō

Y. 34.12
‘Show us trough truth the paths of good thought, easy to pass’
Consequently, in a passage of Plato’s Phaedrus (253de) the horse that possesses aretḗ is opposed to the skoliós (σκολιός) ‘crooked’ one:

 

ἀρετὴ δὲ τίς τοῦἀγαθοῦἢ κακοῦ κακία […] νῦν δὲ λεκτέον. ὁ µὲν τοίνυν αὐτοῖν […] εἶδος ὀρθὸς καὶ διηρθρωµένος […] κελεύσµατι µόνον καὶ λόγῳἡνιοχεῖται· ὁ δ’ αὖ σκολιός […] µάστιγι µετὰ κέντρων µόγις ὑπείκων
Plato Phaedrus 253de
‘We have now to define […] what the goodness of the one and the badness of the other is. The one of them […] is upright and has clean limbs […] he is guided only by the word of command and by reason. Instead, the other is crooked […] hardly obedient to whip and spurs’
Analogously, Vedic r̥tá– is mentioned as the opposite of ‘crooked things’ in R̥gveda 4.23.8b r̥tásya dhītír vr̥jinā́ ni hanti ‘the vision of truth smashes the crooked’.
In conclusion, the term aretḗ (ἀρετή), ‘excellence’ can be traced back to *(H)ar- ‘to fit, join’ which underlies Greek ararískō (ἀραρίσκω) ‘fit’, harmózō (ἁρμόζω) ‘join’ and probably árnumai (ἄρνυμαι) ‘win’. The form *(H)ar-etéh2 parallels *(H)r̥-tó- and *(H)ar-tó-, which are reflected by Vedic r̥tá- and Avestan ašạ– ‘justice, rightness, truth’. The analysis of common associations and collocations supports that aretḗ (ἀρετή) matches Vedic r̥tá- and Avestan ašạ- almost perfectly.
Massetti, L. 2013–2014. “Gr. ἀρετή, ved. r̥tá-, av. aṣ̌a– e l’eccellenza come ordine aggiustato.” Münchener Studien zur Sprachwissenschaft 67.2:123–148.
———. [in preparation]. Phraseologie und indogermanische Dichtersprache in der Sprache der griechischen Chorlyrik: Pindar und Bakchylides.
Melchert, Craig H. 1999. “‘(Zu-)eignung’ in Anatolian and Indo-European.” Studia Celtica et Indogermanica: Festschrift für Wolfgang Meid zum 70. Geburtstag, eds. Peter Anreiter and Erzsébet Jerem, 243–247. Budapest.
Nagy, Gregory. 2017. A sampling of comments on the Iliad and Odyssey. Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.essay:Nagy.A_Sampling_of_Comments_on_the_Iliad_and_Odyssey.2017.
Prellwitz, Walter. 1931. “Zur griechischen Etymologie. ἐτάζω, ἑταῖρος, ἑτοῖμος, ἀρετή.” Glotta 19:85–89.
Vine, Brent. 1998. Aeolic ρπετον and Deverbative * etó in Greek and Indo-European. Innsbruck.
Watkins, Calvert. 1979. “Is tre fir flathemon: marginalia to Audacht Morainn.” Ériu 30:181–190.
 
Laura Massetti 2018.11.15
Ἀργεϊφόντης (Argeïphóntēs)
Argeïphóntēs (Ἀργεϊφόντης) is an agent noun, which commonly designates Hermes. In the hexameter poetry it applies exclusively to this Olympian god and is mostly preceded by other epithets, namely: diáktoros (διάκτορος, usually understood as ‘messenger’, but probably of different meaning), kratús (κρατύς, ‘mighty’), eǘskopos (εΰσκοπος, ‘well visible’ or ‘keen-sighted/well gazing’), khrusórrapis (χρυσόρραπις, ‘possessing a golden wand’), Kullḗnios (Κυλλήνιος, ‘Kyllenios’), klutós (κλυτός, ‘famed’), kúdimos (κύδιμος, ‘marvelous’), compare

αὐτὰρ ἄρα Ζεὺς δῶκε διακτόρῳ ἀργεϊφόντῃ·
Ἑρμείας δὲ ἄναξ δῶκεν Πέλοπι πληξίππῳ
Then Zeus gave it [: the golden scepter] to the diáktoros Argeïphóntēs and Hermes, the lord, gave it to Pelops driver of horses.
Iliad 2.103–104
Since Antiquity, Argeïphóntēs has been interpreted in different ways. The second compound member -phóntēs was prevalently connected to the verb theínō, ‘to slay/kill’ (θείνω). The first compound member Argeï- was diversely explained, namely: (i) as the reflex of the mythological name Árgos (Ἄργος) or (ii) as the reflex of the word argẽs ‘snake’ (ἀργῆς).
(i) The majority of ancient sources associate Argeïphóntēs with the mythological episode of Io: Árgos is an ‘all-seeing’ guardian, whom jealous Hera had put on Io’s watch, after she had changed the maiden’s form into a cow. When Zeus sent Hermes to steal Io, he killed Árgos, and thus became ‘the killer of Árgos ’, compare

Διὸς δὲ ἐπιτάξαντος Ἑρμῇ κλέψαι τὴν βοῦν, μηνύσαντος Ἱέρακος, ἐπειδὴ λαθεῖν οὐκ ἠδύνατο, λίθῳ βαλὼν ἀπέκτεινε τὸν Ἄργον, ὅθεν ἀργεϊφόντης ἐκλήθη
Zeus ordered Hermes to steal the cow, but he could not hide, because Hierax had revealed (the plan). So he hit Árgos with a stone and killed him, whence he is called Argeïphóntēs (Argus-slayer).
[Apollodorus] 2.7.5
(ii) According to Pausanias, Argeïphóntēs meant ‘killer of the snake.’ This interpretation must have been synchronically perceived as plausible, as, Sophocles (Tragicorum Graecorum Fragmenta IV 1024) applies the epithet to Apollo, the killer of Python, compare

ἀργεïφόντης· ὁ ὀφιοκτόνος. ἀργῆν γὰρ ἔνιοι τὸν ὄφιν καλοῦσιν
Argeïphóntēs : the ‘snake-killer’, for some call the snake argẽs
Pausanias, fragment 143 E

A less well-attested exegetic tradition explains -phóntēs as a derivative of phaínō ‘to (make) appear’ (φαίνω), compare

ἀργειφόντης· καθαροφόντης λευκοφόντης. ἢ ἐν Ἄργει πρῶτον πεφηνώς
Argeiphóntēs : pure from killing, white-shining, or having first appeared in Argos
Hesychius α 7037 Latte-Cunningham
Modern-day interpretations of Argeïphóntēs partly align with the ones provided by scholars in Antiquity. To begin with, there is general agreement on explaining argeï- as a derivative of the root *h2erĝ- ‘bright (and speed) as the light’, underlying the mythological name Árgos (Ἄργος), a substantivized form of the adjective argós ‘shining with the speed of light’ (translation by Nagy 2017) through accent retraction. An s-stem *h2erĝ-es- underlies both argẽs ‘snake’ and the second compound member -argḗs, compare enargḗs ‘visible’ (ἐναργής). The first compound member Argeï- in Argeïphóntēs bears resemblance to the dative of such a stem, which speaks in favor of a meaning ‘with/by way of light-speed or whiteness/brilliance.’
There is no agreement on the possible etymology and meaning of the second compound member -phóntēs. A connection between -phóntēs and the Indo-European root *gu̯hen- ‘to kill, slay’ has been repeatedly supported. In his commentary to Odyssey 17.292, Nagy (2017) argues for a meaning ‘killing by way of speeding light’. Furthermore, he points out a mythological parallel between the story of Hermes ‘killer of Argus’ and that of Irish hero Cú Chulainn (‘Hound of Culann’). According to the myth found in Recension 1 of The Cattle Raid of Cooley (http://celt.ucc.ie/published/T301012/index.html, p. 142), Cú Chulainn kills the watchdog of the smith Culann and consequently assumes a role comparable to that of Hermes as ‘protector of sheep and cattle’ (compare Homeric Hymn 4.2, 14). The Irish hero seems to undertake some distinctive prerogatives of his victim, as he promises to protect the smith’s herds of cattle and flocks of sheep after killing of the Culann’s watchdog. Significantly, the former name of Cú Chulainn is Sétantae, ‘knower of the sét ‘road[s]’ (compare Ó hUiginn 2006:508), a trait which overlaps with a standard attribute of Hermes (compare Homeric Hymn 4.303, σὺ δ’ αὖθ’ ὁδὸν ἡγεμονεύσεις ‘you will lead the road’). Nagy concludes that ‘in the case of Hermes, the myth about his killing Argos, who can be seen as a monstrous canine version of his other self, signals the god’s absolutized powers of perception and recognition.’ Following up on this brilliant interpretative input and establishing a connection with the etymology supported below, I would rather argue that Hermes and Árgos are rivals in shining. Thus, they resemble each other and are each other’s archenemy at the same time.
As previously pointed out, this interpretation of Argeïphóntēs is synchronically true. The mythological parallel brought forth by Nagy (2017) thus stands as convincing. Nevertheless, as also pointed out by Nagy (2017), it is unlikely that Argeïphóntēs meant ‘killer of Argos/the (dog) Argos/the bright(spotted) dog’ (compare West 1978:368–369). It is difficult to explain how a first compound member argo- (ἀργο-) came to be reshaped as argeï- (ἀργεϊ-). Additionally, it is certainly true that Hermes is a dog-killer, compare the epithet kunághēs (κυνάγχης ‘dog-strangler’), found in Hipponax fragment 3a.1 West. However, the most ancient sources covering Io’s story never describe or portray Argus as a dog (compare LIMC ‘Hera’, ‘Hermes’, ‘Io’). Similar criticisms can be raised against the interpretation ‘killer of the snake’, first championed by Davis 1953 (compare also Pelliccia in Watkins 1995:383–385): one would not expect a first compound member argei- to have the value of an accusative, i.e., ‘snake-killing’. When compounds exhibit a first member in -ει to a s -stem, this usually retains the value of a delocatival or deinstrumental dative as opposed to first compound members reflecting different case-forms, compare the pair enkheibrómos ‘having the thunder in the spear’ (Pindar Olympian 7.43) and enkhésphoros ‘spear-bearing’ (Pindar Nemean 3.61). Finally, Io’s guardian Árgos is never portrayed as a snake.
Differently, Koller (1976) makes the case that -phóntēs is to be traced back to the Indo-European root *bheh2 ‘to shine’, underlying Greek phaínō ‘to become visible’ and pháos ‘light.’ Koller (1976) proposes that at the basis of Argeïphóntēs lies a collocation of type kálleï … stílbōn (κάλλεϊ … στίλβων ‘shining of/in beauty’, Iliad 3.392), kúdeï … gaíōn (κύδεϊ γαίων ‘rejoicing of/in glory’, compare Iliad 1.405), sthéneï … blemeaínōn (σθένεϊ βλεμεαίνων ‘swelling of strength’, Iliad 9.237), and the river name Puriphlegéthōn (Πυριφλεγέθων, ‘flaming of fire’, Iliad 8.337), i.e. a collocation in which a de-instrumental dative is joined with a participle form. According to this theory, Argeïphóntēs would exist besides an unattested argeïphõn in the same way as Kleophónēs ‘shining of glory’ (Herodianus) is attested besides Kleophõn ‘shining of glory’ (Inscriptiones Graecae ii2 2283, Attica). Argeïphóntēs should thus be understood as the result of the metrical adaptation of an unattested form argeïphõn, which would ultimately go back to the univerbation of a collocation árgeï pháōn ‘shining in/of bright light’. The premises of this etymological proposal are plausible, but the details of this hypothesis should be clarified and partially corrected:

  1. It is unlikely that *pháōn would contract into *phõn and appear as such in Greek hexameter poetry: *pháōn would probably have been spelled as disyllabic, maybe with diektasis, *phóōn. However, a univerbized form as *Argeïpháōn or *Argeïphóōn could have been reshaped into Argeïphóntēs to comply with the requirements of Greek hexameter.
  2. If a form *-phõn existed it could have reflected a new formation on *bhn̥- or phan-, that is to say, a reshaping which took place when the vowel alternance a/o had not yet been abandoned as a synchronic regularity, as proposed by Peters (1993:104, fn. 84).
In any case, *Argeïpháōn or *Argeïphóōn might have been remodeled into Argeïphóntēs under the influence of other compounds with a second member -phóntēs ‘killer’, especially because the prevalent synchronic interpretation of the epithet was ‘killer of Argus’ (see above).
The phraseological comparison with an Old Indic epithet of the fire-god Agni provides further support to this hypothesis. Old Indic bhā́r̥jīka- ‘whose radiance is white appearance’ is an exclusive epithet of Agni, compare

adyā́ dūtáṃ vr̥ṇīmahe , vásum agním purupriyám
dhūmáketum bhā́r̥jīkaṃ víyùṣṭiṣu , yajñā́nām adhvaraśríyam
Today we choose as messenger Agni the good one, dear to many, whose beacon is smoke, but whose white appearance is shining (bhā́r̥jīka-) when the dawns break, the glory of the ceremonies, of the sacrifices.
Rigveda 1.44.3, translation by Jamison – Brereton 2014, modified by me
The epithet is a compound based on the same lexical material as Argeïphóntēs: the first member bhā́- reflects bhā́s- (Schindler 1972:32), based on Indo-European *bheh2 ‘to shine, become visible’, compare Vedic bhā ‘to radiate’, Greek phaínō. The second member r̥jīka-* is itself a compound (compare Thieme 1948:40, footnote 2): the first compound member r̥ji- matches Avestan ərəzi-, Greek argi-, reflecting *h2r̥ĝ-i- ‘bright, white’, while the second member reflects *-h3ko-, compare Greek -ōpos (-ωπος ‘appearance, what appears/is visible’).
The match between Greek Argeiphóntēs and Vedic bhā́r̥jīka- is almost perfect: both compounds are exclusive epithets of Hermes and Agni, who share a variety of other distinctive prerogatives (as a recent reference compare Massetti 2021). Furthermore, the forms display constituent elements which derive from Indo-European * bheh2 ‘to shine, become visible’ and Indo-European * h2erĝ- ‘white.’ We can conclude that the comparative analysis supports that Hermes Argeiphóntēs is the god ‘shining with brilliance/white light.’
Davis, S. 1953. “ Argeiphontes in Homer. The dragon-slayer.” Greece and Rome 22.33–38.
Jamison, S.W., and J.P. Brereton. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. 3 vols. Oxford & New York.
LIMC = Foundation for the LIMC, eds. 1990. Lexicon Iconographicum Mythologiae Classicae. Vol. 5, 1–2. Herakles–Kenchrias. Vol. 7, 1–2. Oidipus–Theseus, 1994. Zürich.
Koller, H. 1976. Ἀργεϊφόντης. Glotta 54.3-4.211–215.
Massetti, L. 2021. “Hermes and Hestia Revisited: Hermes ἀκάκητα and the Funerary Fire.” In Proceedings of the 31st Annual UCLA Indo-European Conference, eds. by David M. Goldstein, Stephanie W. Jamison, and Brent Vine, 197–213. Bremen.
Massetti, L. 2022. “Hermes Ἀργεϊφόντης and Agni bhā́r̥jīka.” Indogermanische Forschungen (in press).
Nagy, G. 2017. A sampling comments on Odyssey Rhapsody 17. Center for Hellenic Studies. https://classical-inquiries.chs.harvard.edu/a-sampling-of-comments-on-odyssey-rhapsody-17/.
Ó hUiginn, F. 2006. Growth and development in the late Ulster Cycle: The case of Táin Bó Flidais. In Memory and the Modern Celtic Literature, ed. J. F. Nagy, 143–161. Dublin.
Peters, M. 1993. “Beiträge zur griechischen Etymologie.” In Miscellanea Linguistica Graeco-Latina, ed. Lambert Isebaert, 85–114. Namur.
Thieme, P. 1948. Untersuchungen zur Wortkunde und Auslegung des Rigveda. Halle/Salle.
Watkins, C. 1995. How to Kill a Dragon. Aspects of Indo-European Poetics. Oxford & New York.
West, M.L. 1978. Hesiod. Works and Days. Oxford.
 
Laura Massetti, 2022.03.15
Ἀριάδνη (Ariadnē)
In discussing the Minoan and Mycenaean signatures in the description of Crete at Odyssey 19. 185-193, Nagy points out that the crucial feature in this description is the mention of Amnisos and the cave of Eileithuia that is located there. Eleithuia at Amnisos is actually attested in a Linear B tablet found at Knossos (Knossos tablet Gg 705 line 1). Nagy argues that there is also evidence for human votaries of this goddess, and the ideal case in point is Ariadne, whose connection to the goddess is signaled by the etymology of her name. According to the Alexandrian dictionary attributed to Hesychius: ἁδνόν· ἁγνόν Κρῆτες ‘the Cretans use the word hadno– for hagno-’. So, since hagno– means ‘holy’, Ariadnē means ‘very holy’.
This etymology of Ariadnē correlates with another entry in the dictionary attributed to Hesychius, which reads: Καλλίχορον· ἐν Κνωσσῷ ἐπὶ τῷ τῆς Ἀριάδνης τόπῳ ‘Kalli-khoron was the name of the place of Ariadne in Knossos’. Kalli-khoron, is ‘the place that is beautiful’, and, as Nagy suggests “the word khoros here can designate either the ‘place’ where singing and dancing takes place or the group of singers and dancers who perform at that place.” Ariadne can be seen as a figure who stands for the girls performing sacred songs and dances in a holy place.
Nagy, G. 2015. “A Cretan Odyssey, Part I.” Classical Inquiries September 17, 2015. http://classical-inquiries.chs.harvard.edu/a-cretan-odyssey-part-1/.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Konnor Clark 12.11.15 and Olga Levaniouk 06.04.16
Ἀσωπός (Asōpós)
It is said that when Zeus abducted the nymph Aegina from the banks of the river Asopos, the river god became so angry that his waters overflowed abnormally as he pursued Zeus, who reacted by striking the waters with his flaming thunderbolt, thus restoring the normal flow of the river. And because the fiery thunderbolt of Zeus made this violent contact with the waters of the river, it is said that even now you can see ánthrakes ’glowing coals’ rising up from the depths of these waters. I quote the relevant wording in the retelling of Apollodorus (3.12.6): Ζεὺς δὲ Ἀσωπὸν μὲν κεραυνώσας διώκοντα πάλιν ἐπὶ τὰ οἰκεῖα ἀπέπεμψε εῖθρα, διὰ τοῦτο μέχρι καὶ νῦν ἐκ τῶν τούτου είθρων ἄνθρακες φέρονται ‘when Asopos pursued Zeus, Zeus struck him with his thunderbolt and thus restored the river to its familiar course, and that is why even to this day there are glowing coals [ánthrakes] produced by the streams of this river’.
The noun Asōpós can be understood as a compound formation meaning basically ‘having the looks of glowing coals’; in this case, the root as in Asōpos is cognate with the root as in the noun asbolos/asbolē, which refers to the sparks emitted by glowing coals.
Such an etymology of the noun Asōpós indicates that the name of the river god is connected to myths of anthropogony. And this connection is validated by the local Aeginetan anthropogonic myth about the god Asopos as the father of the nymph Aegina, who in turn is the Mother Earth that generates the first human in the land of Aegina.
Nagy, G. 2011. “Asopos and his multiple daughters: Traces of preclassical epic in the Aeginetan Odes of Pindar.” Aegina: Contexts for Choral Lyric Poetry. Myth, History, and Identity in the Fifth Century BC, ed. David Fearn, 41–78. Oxford. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.essay:Nagy.Asopos_and_His_Multiple_Daughters.2011.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Daniel Miller 2015.11.20
Βελλεροφόντης, Βελλέροφῶν (Bellerophóntēs, Bellerophôn) and Ἐλλεροφόντης (Ellerophóntēs)
Bellerophóntēs, (Βελλεροφόντης, short form Bellerophôn, Greek Βελλέροφῶν) is the name of the Argive hero credited with the slaughtering of the Chimaera (Greek χίμαιρα ‘goat’). In the sixth book of the Iliad, we learn through Glaucus’s words that his ancestor Bellerophóntēs, a descendant of Sisyphus, is sent to Lycia by Proetus after Proetus’s wife Anteia (called Stheneboia in other versions of the same story) falsely accuses him of raping her. When the king of Lycians, who is Anteia’s father and Bellerophontes’s host, finds out about his daughter’s accusations, he first sends off Bellerophontes to accomplish three dangerous tasks (namely: [1] the killing of the Chimaera, [2] the battle against the Solumoi, and [3] the battle against the Amazons, compare also Pindar Olympian 13.84–90, which relies on Iliad 6.179–186 as a narrative model), then tries to ambush the hero on his way back to Lycia (compare Iliad 6.184–190). Bellerophontes manages to survive to the king’s murderous attempts and finally marries his daughter, who gives birth to his three children: Isandros, Hippolochus (Glaucus’s father), and Laodamia (Sarpedon’s mother).
Since Antiquity, the name of Bellerophóntēs was interpreted as ‘Killer of Belleros’, i.e., as a compound name featuring a second member -phóntēs ‘killer’, compare

Βελλεροφόντην· […] Βέλλερον δὲ ἱππικῇ φονεύσας οὕτως ὠνόμασται.
Scholia in Iliadem 6.155b
Bellerophóntēs : having killed Belleros on the horse, he has been named so.”
The identification of Belleros, however, is problematic: a character with this name apparently plays no role in any of the versions of Bellerophontes’s myth in our possession. Ancient scholars attempted to identify this ghost-figure as a Corinthian man, whom the Bellerophontes had killed before being hosted by Proetus. However, this explanation looks more like an ad hoc narrative creation, tailored by ancient commentators to provide the opaque back-formed name Belleros with a meaningful background story than as the reflex of an actual lost narrative.
Several alternative explanations have been suggested by modern scholars: Kretschmer (1948) put forth the proposal to identify Greek Bélleros as a local demon, eponymous of the landscape Pelleritis, infesting the Corinthian-Argive border area; Bonfante (1969: 188) proposed to connect Bélleros with a ‘Balkan’ terms meaning ‘dragon’, such as Romanian baláur. By contrast, Katz (1998), pointing out that the name of the hero is actually preserved as Ellerophóntēs by Zenodotus (Eustathius, Commentarii ad Homeri Iliadem 1.446.21), managed to etymologize Ellerophóntēs in ‘Indo-European terms’, providing an explanation which fits well Bellerophontes’s heroic career. In this scenario, however, we will still have to assume that the name Bellerophóntēs is the result of a Greek reshaping and/or re-adaptation of the name, maybe due to secondary connection with one of the names mentioned above (the ethnographic name Pelleritis, baláur or the like).
As already anticipated, it is safe to say that the second compound member – phóntēs etymologically belongs to the Indo-European root *gu̯hen- ‘to slay, kill’, which, among others, underlies the Mycenaean second compound member -qo-ta / -kontās /, the Greek thematic present theínō (θείνω) and the reduplicated thematic aorist épephnen (ἔπεφνεν), the Hittite preterit form kuenta ‘he killed’, and the Old Indic root han ‘to kill/slay’. Specifically, the compounds with a second member -phóntēs or – phontās ‘killer’ have been recently interpreted by Nussbaum (2021:403, footnote 32) as resulting from the analogical remodeling of a participial second member—that is, in our case, *-φων, *-φον- —through the addition of the Greek agentive suffix *-tā- (the kind of suffix seen in names like Greek naútēs ‘sailor’).
The first compound member Ellero- may be etymologically related to a variety of terms or compound members, which apply to ‘water-serpents’ or ‘watery’ places, namely: Latin anguīlla, the ‘serpent (angui-, compare Latin anguis) eel (-illa)’; Greek énkh-elus (ἔγχ-ελυς) ‘water-snake’, Hittite illuy / illui-, the first compound member of the name MUŠIlluy-anka, the monster defeated by the Hittite Storm-god (cf. Watkins 1995:321), and the Hittite substantive ellueššar ‘snake-pit’ (Watkins 1985: 251) or ‘freshwater’ (Katz 1998: 324). Greek –elus (as in énkhelus), Hittite illuy- or illui- and Greek Ellero- (as in Ellerophóntēs) all exhibit word-formations which can be framed in the so-called ‘Caland-System’, a system of suffix-replacements transversally productive within all the Indo-European languages. The following ‘Caland-like’ formations are indeed recognizable:

– an u-stem: the Greek second compound member –elus,
– an i-first compound member: Hittite illuy- or illui-, and
– am -(e)ro-stem: the Greek first compound member Ellero-.
According to this theory, the first compound Ellero- should be interpreted as adjectival, i.e., ‘watery’. The hero’s name Ellerophóntēs would thus reflect ‘killer of the watery (creature)’ and would be built with the same lexical material as the Hittite sequence ‘(the Storm) god killed Illuy-anka’, compare:

DIM-aš uit nu=kan MUŠilluy[(ankan)]
kuenta DINGIR MEŠ-š=a katti=šši ešer
Significantly, in Iliad 6, Glaucus describes the Bellerophontes’s accomplishments through the verb theínō (compare πεφνέμεν, at 180, κατέπεφνε, at 183), while the Chimaera as a hybrid creature, having a snake tail (ὄπιθεν δὲ δράκων, at 181), compare

πρῶτον μέν ῥα Χίμαιραν ἀμαιμακέτην ἐκέλευσε
πεφνέμεν· ἣ δ᾽ ἄρ᾽ ἔην θεῖον γένος οὐδ᾽ ἀνθρώπων,
πρόσθε λέων, ὄπιθεν δὲ δράκων, μέσση δὲ χίμαιρα,
δεινὸν ἀποπνείουσα πυρὸς μένος αἰθομένοιο,
καὶ τὴν μὲν κατέπεφνε θεῶν τεράεσσι πιθήσας.

Iliad 6.179–183
“First (the king of Lycia) bade him (Bellerophontes) to slay the raging Chimaera. She was of divine stock, not of men: lion in front, snake behind, and goat in the middle, breathing forth the terrible might of blazing fire. And he slayed her, trusting in the prodigies of the gods.”
If Katz (1998) is correct in reconstructing that a sequence *(B)Ellero-ophi-phóntēs ‘killer of the eel-/water-snake’, matching Hittite MUŠIlluy-ankan kuenta ‘he killed the monster (MUŠ[scilicet named]) Water-Snake’, lies at the basis of the name (B)Ellerophóntēs, we may argue that the semantic focus of the first compound member Ellero- in Ellerophóntēs corresponds to the dragon-component of the Chimaera.
Still, one may wonder if this assumption is completely correct. After all, the name Chimaera seems to emphasize a quadruped component of the monster, the goat-body part (Greek χίμαιρα ‘goat’). Could then the Chimaera be interpreted as a sort of water-goat or water-quadruped monster? In order to verify this hypothesis a few remarks on the Chimaera’s mythological genealogy are in order.
A mythological relative of Tuphṓn and Húdrā, the Chimaera is a hybrid, fire-blasting creature (compare Blanc 2006), provided with a threefold body (see Iliad 6.181, quoted above) or three different heads.

ἣ δὲ Χίμαιραν ἔτικτε πνέουσαν ἀμαιμάκετον πῦρ,
δεινήν τε μεγάλην τε ποδώκεά τε κρατερήν τε·
τῆς δ᾽ ἦν τρεῖς κεφαλαί· μία μὲν χαροποῖο λέοντος,
ἣ δὲ χιμαίρης, ἣ δ᾽ ὄφιος, κρατεροῖο δράκοντος

Hesiod Theogony 319–322
“That one gave birth to the Chimaera, who could blast blazing fire, terrible, big, swift-footed and might. That one (i.e., the Chimaera) had three heads: one of a grim lion, one of a goat, and one of a snake, a mighty dragon.”
While Hesiod clearly states that the Chimaera is the daughter of Tuphṓn, the identification of the monster’s mother is a debated matter (cf. West 1966: 254–255): in the Hesiodic passage quoted above, the nominative feminine ḗ dé (Greek ἣ δέ) may refer to the Echidna (Hesiod Theogony 304) or to the Hydra (Hesiod Theogony 314). If the Echidna were the mother of the Chimaera, the link between Chimaera and the snakes could be well founded, since the Echidna (Greek Ἔχιδνα) bears a speaking name based on the Greek term for ‘viper’, ékhis (Greek ἔχις). Conversely, if we imagine that it is the Hydra who gave birth to the Chimaera, as it is more likely given that Greek Húdra is the closest feminine name to ḗ dé in the Hesiodic text, we may frame the Chimaera’s description within an inherited system of mythological water-quadruped-monsters found in other Indo-European traditions. To be sure, the Hydra is commonly imagined to be many-headed, just like the Chimaera, and came to be represented as a serpentine being since an early age (compare the Boeotian fibula from circa 700 BCE preserved at British Museum: https://www.britishmuseum.org/collection/object/G_1898-1118-1). However, as R. Ginevra emphasizes (see Húdra), Hesiod makes the Hydra the sister of two canid monsters: Othros, who is Geryon’s dog, and Kerberos, the three-headed watchdog of the underworld. The name of the Hydra, being itself a feminine adjective derived from the term for ‘water’, húdōr (Greek ὕδωρ), might have primarily applied to a canid monster (cf. Nagy 1985–1986). If the feminine adjective húdra primarily designated the ‘she-hound/dog of the waters’, the mythological name of the monster would semantically parallel those of other canid-like monsters who infest waters, found in the Scandinavian and Celtic traditions, namely: the Irish monster-name On-chú ‘Water-dog’ (Caithréim Cellaig) and the Old Norse Fenris-ulfr (Gylfaginning 34, on which see Ginevra 2018:285). In this connection, it is significant that the choir of Euripides’ Heracles calls the Hydra as ‘the dog of Lerna’:

τήν τ᾽ ἀμφίκρανον καὶ παλιμβλαστῆ κύνα
ὕδραν φονεύσας …

Euripides Heracles 1274–1275
“Having killed the she-hound whose many heads on all sides grow back again, the Hydra.”
I want to highlight here that the sequence (κύνα) ὕδραν φονεύσας semantically matches the collocation underlying Ellero-phóntēs, namely ‘to kill’ (-phóntēs, phoneúsas, derivatives of Indo-European *gu̯hen-) and a -(e)ro-adjective belonging to the semantic field of ‘water’ (húdra, Ellero-). The passage in questions thus prompts (i) the hypothesis that the Chimaera might have inherited some of her hybrid components (in particular, her association with quadrupeds) from the Hydra, and (ii) the reconstruction of the phraseology ‘kill(er) (of the) water-monster’ as underlying the mythological name Ellerophóntēs.
The presented linguistic and comparative evidence concerning (B)Ellerophóntēs and the Chimaera thus supports the reconstruction of the hero’s inherited background and his identification as the quintessential ‘killer of the water-(snake or quadruped-)monster’.
Blanc, A. 2006. “Lancer du feu » en grec: etude de phraseologie (autour de πυρπνόος et πυρπόλος).” La langue poétique indo-européenne. Actes du Colloque de travail de la Société des Études Indo-Européennes. Paris, 22-24 octobre 2003. Eds. D. Petit and G. J. Pinault. Leuven-Paris.
Bonfante, G. 1969. Review of Chantraine 1968. Rivista di Filologia 97.185–190.
Ginevra, R. 2018. Fraseologia e onomastica nella Vǫluspá a confronto con le lingue indoeuropee di più antica attestazione / Phraseologie und Onomastik in der Vǫluspá im Vergleich mit den altindogermanischen Sprachen. PhD diss., Università per Stranieri di Siena and Universität zu Köln.
Katz, J. 1998. “How to be a Dragon in Indo-European. Hittite illuyaankaš and its Linguistic and Cultural Congeners in Latin, Greek, and Germanic.” Mír Curad. Studies in Honor of Clavert Watkins, eds. J. Jasanoff, H.C. Melchert, and L. Oliver, 317–334. Innsbruck.
Kretschmer, P. 1948 (1951). “Bellerophontes.” Glotta 31.92–103, 246–247.
Nagy, J. 1985-1986. “Otter, Salmon and Eel in Traditional Gaelic Narrative.” Studia Celtica 20-21.123–144.
Nussbaum, A. 2021. “Persephonology and Persemorphology. Περσεφόνη/Φερροφαττα etc. ‘Sheaf Thresher’ reanalyzed.” In l yuke wmer ra: Indo-European Studies in Honor of Georges-Jean Pinault, eds. by H. A. Fellner, M. Malzahn, and M. Peyrot, 391–403. Ann Arbor/New York.
Watkins, C. 1985. “Hittite and Indo-European Studies.” Münchener Studien zur Sprachwissenschaft 45:245–255.
———. 1995. How to Kill a Dragon. Aspects of Indo-European Poetics. Oxford.
West, M. 1966. Hesiod. Theogony. Oxford.
 
Laura Massetti, 2022.05.14
Δάειρα, Δαῖρα (Dáeira, Daîra)
The name Dáeira (Δάειρα) or Daîra (Δαῖρα), with contraction, belongs to a mysterious female deity, who was worshipped in the Eleusinian rites. The goddess is mostly connected with the realm of the dead by ancient literary sources. According to a fragment by Aeschylus (fragment 277 Radt) Daîra is Persephone; differently, Aristophanes identifies her as Semele’s mother (fragment 804 Kassel–Austin). Apollonius of Rhodes (3.847) identifies her with Hecate, while Lycophron (Alexandra 706–710) mentions her as Hades’ spouse. According to Pausanias (1.38.7), Dáeira is the wife of Hermes and the mother of Eleusis/Eleusinos, the eponymous Attic hero.
The identification of the goddess with Persephone or Hecate is consistent with the synchronic etymological explanations of the name, which connected it to the term daḯs ‘torch’. Indeed, both Persephone and Hecate associated with the gesture of ‘torch-bearing’, compare Etymologicum Genuinum, under Δάειρα: ἡ Περσεφόνη παρὰ Ἀθηναίοις, παρὰ τὴν δᾷδα, ἐπειδὴ μετὰ δάιδων ἐπιτελεῖται αὐτῆς τὰ μυστήρια, ἢ ὅτι δαῖδα φορεῖ ‘[Dáeira:] Persephone according to the Athenians, because of [the term] dâida [torch], because her rites are celebrated with torches, or because she bears torches’; Bacchylides, fragment 1b.1 Maehler Ἑκάτα δαϊδοφόρε ‘torch-bearer Hecate.’
Modern etymologies (Frisk 1960:338, Beekes 2009:295–296) support a connection with the Indo-European root * dens – ‘to become wise’, which underlies the Greek verb δαῆναι ‘to learn’ and Sanskrit dasrá- ‘effecting miracles’. Although, from a merely linguistic point of view, nothing speaks against this proposal, texts provide no support for Dáeira as the ‘Knowing goddess.’
It is more likely, however, that Dáeira / Daîra has to be kept apart from daḯs ‘torch’ and daênai ‘to learn’. As Alexander Nikolaev points out, Pherecydes tells us that Dáeira was associated to the idea of ‘moistness’ by the ancient ones (palaioí), compare:

Ἐπὶ γὰρ ὑγρᾶς οὐσίας τάττουσιν οἱ παλαιοὶ τὴν Δάειραν
‘For the ancient ones assign to Dáeira the power over moistness’

(Pherecydes fragment 45 Fowler)

One may add that Dáeira’s connection to ‘water’ is also reflected by her mythological pedigree. According to Pherecydes (fragment 45 Fowler) she is the sister of River Styx, while Pausanias (1.38.7) identifies her as the daughter of Okeanos. All these data provide support for Nikolaev’s (2019) etymology: Dáeira is a substantivized feminine adjective of the same type as Greek píeira, Sanskrit pī́varī ‘fat’, with a suffix *-u̯er-ih2 entangling a possessive meaning ‘having/possessing X.’ The basis *da- of Dá-(w)eira could be connected with the same root figuring in several names of rivers or mythological/divine figures linked to the element ‘water’, such as OInd. Dānu- (name of the water serpent Vr̥tra), Scythian Tanais, Irish Danu, Welsh Don, Lithuanian Dunōjus, Latvian Duņavas, Germanic Danube, and the Greek god’s name Poseidon (Poseidáōn), which is commonly etymologized as ‘Lord of the Water(s)’ (maybe reflecting an univerbation of a vocative ‘O Lord of the Waters!’).

To sum up: Dáeira or Daîra, daughter of the Ocean and sister of the Stynx, is to be identified as the ‘Lady of the Waters.’
Beekes, R. 2010. Etymological Dictionary of Greek. Leiden / Boston: Brill.
Frisk, H. 1960. Griechisches etymologisches Wörterbuch. 1. Band (Α–Κ). Heidelberg: Winter.
Nikolaev, A. ΔΑΕΙΡΑ, the lady of the waters. In: Nikolai Kazanski (ed.): Indo-European Linguistics and Classical Philology XXIII. Proceedings of the 23rd Conference in Memory of Professor Joseph M. Tronsky, June 24–26, 2019, 790–795. Saint Petersburg: Nauka.
 
Laura Massetti 2021.05.03
δαίς (dais)
A. Nagy comments on the notion of ‘division’ latent in daís and overt in the Homeric expression δαιτὸς ἐίσης ‘of an equal daís’.
“Not just for Achilles but for any Homeric character, the eating of meat at feasts is by nature a sacrificial occasion: in the words of George M. Calhoun, “every meal was a sacrifice and an act of worship, and every sacrifice a meal.” This statement may be overly one-dimensional in its view of epic action, but it remains a valid observation about the contents of Homeric narrative: feasts where meat is consumed are indeed regularly occasioned by sacrifice. The Homeric word for such occasions is daís/daítē (e.g. Odyssey 3.33/44, etc.), and both nouns are etymologically derived from the verb daíomai ‘divide, apportion, allot’. Consider the following Homeric collocation of verb and noun:

 

μοίρας δασσάμενοι δαίνυντ᾽ ἐρικυδέα δαῖτα
Odyssey 3.66
Apportioning moírai [portions], they feasted a very glorious daís [feast].
The notion of ‘division’ latent in daís becomes overt in expressions involving δαιτὸς ἐίσης ‘of an equal daís’ (as at Iliad 1.468, 1.602; 2.431; 7.320; 23.56)—denoting situations where everyone has his proper share at the sacrificial feast.”
Nagy, G. 1979. “The Death of Pyrrhos.” Chapter 7 of The Best of the Achaeans: Concepts of the Hero in Archaic Greek Poetry. Baltimore. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_NagyG.The_Best_of_the_Achaeans.1999.
Calhoun, G. M. 1962. “Polity and Society: The Homeric Picture.” A Companion to Homer, ed. A. J. B. Wace and F. Stubbings, 431–452. London.
B. Achilles has a special relationship to the daís, which is shared by all of this heroic lineage, the Aeacids. The key to this special relationship is the etymological connection of daís to the idea of division and distribution.
“Is there, then, a special relationship of Achilles to the daís? Certainly this seems to be so not only in the case of Achilles but also in the case of all his heroic lineage, according to the Hesiodic passage that describes the Aeacids as follows:

 

… πολέμῳ κεχαρηότας ἠΰτε δαιτί
Hesiod fr. 206MW
… delighting in war as well as in the daís
The key to such a close relationship of the Aeacids to the daís is the etymological connection of the word with the notion inherent in daíomai ‘divide, apportion, allot’. This notion constitutes a mythological theme that runs through the whole line of Aeacids, starting with the prime ancestor himself. The hero Aiakos, in the words of Pindar, was so fair and just as to be worthy of settling matters pertaining to the gods themselves:

 

Αἰακὸν … κεδνό-
τατον ἐπιχθονίων. ὃ καὶ
δαιμόνεσσι δίκας ἐπείραινε

 

Pindar Isthmian 8.22–24
Aiakos … the most cherished of mortals,
who rendered díkai [judgments, justice] even for the gods
The correlation here of the word díkē with the concept of making fair allotments reminds us of the wording used to describe how the honor of Achilles himself is to be tested one more time in the Iliad. As the actual setting for Agamemnon’s final offer of compensation to Achilles in return for having at the outset deprived him of his fair share, Odysseus proposes the holding of a special daís:

 

αὐτὰρ ἔπειτά σε δαιτὶ ἐνὶ κλισίῃς ἀρεσάσθω
πιείρῃ, ἵνα μή τι δίκης ἐπιδευὲς ἔχῃσθα

 

Iliad 19.179–180
But let him [Agamemnon] make amends to you [Achilles] with a rich daís in the tents,
so that you may have no lack in díkē.
It is at this dais, when Achilles is to be tested one more time with the compensation offered by Agamemnon (Iliad 19.268–281), that he even bids his fellow Achaeans to go and feast (Iliad 19.275)—though without his participation. As we now follow the line of Aiakos down to his son Peleus, the association of the Aeacids with the themes of the daís becomes more involved. The singular occasion for the daís of Peleus, where the Olympian gods themselves attended, was the feast of his wedding with Thetis—a traditional theme celebrated by the Cypria as an appropriate setting for the onset of the entire Trojan Cycle (Proclus 102.14–15 Allen). At this daís celebrating a marriage that led to the conception of Achilles himself, Zeus willed that Éris ‘Strife’ would bring about a neîkos ‘quarrel’ among the gods; these specific themes of éris/neîkos at a daís constitute the opening scene of the Cypria in particular and of the Trojan Cycle in general (Proclus 102.13–19: Éris/neîkos at 14/15). Short range, these themes are appropriate to the motivation of the Trojan War; long range, the very same themes also provide a setting for the evolution of Achilles as a heroic figure.”
Nagy, G. 1979. “The Death of Pyrrhos.” Chapter 7 of The Best of the Achaeans: Concepts of the Hero in Archaic Greek Poetry. Baltimore. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_NagyG.The_Best_of_the_Achaeans.1999.
C. Nagy discusses the metonymic meaning of the word daís, which encompasses the whole sequence of events typical of festivals. A case in point is Odyssey 9.3–12.
“As Odysseus himself says later on in Odyssey ix, when he finally identifies himself, there is in fact no greater gratification in the whole world that the combination of good feasting and good singing, and the model for the general reference to singing here is the singer Demodokos:

 

|3 This is indeed a beautiful thing, to listen to a singer [aoidós] |4 such as this one [= Demodokos], the kind of singer that he is, comparable to the gods with the sound of his voice [audḗ], |5 for I declare, there is no outcome [télos] that has more pleasurable beauty [kháris] |6 than the moment when the spirit of festivity [euphrosúnē] prevails throughout the whole community [dêmos] |7 and the people at the feast [daitumónes], throughout the halls, are listening to the singer [aoidós] |8 as they sit there—you can see one after the other—and they are seated at tables that are filled |9 with grain and meat, while wine from the mixing bowl is drawn |10 by the one who pours the wine and takes it around, pouring it into their cups. |11 This kind of thing, as I see it in my way of thinking, is the most beautiful thing in the whole world.
Odyssey 9.3–12
The feast that is going on here is a continuation of the feast that is already signaled by the word daís at line 429 of Odyssey viii, which basically means ‘feast’. In that context, daís refers short-range to an occasion of communal dining (dórpon ‘dinner’: 395), which will take place after sunset (417). The intended guest of honor at this feast will be Odysseus. This occasion of communal dining leads into the third song of Demodokos (484–485). But this same word daís at line 429 of Odyssey viii is also making a long-range reference: it refers metonymically to a stylized festival that has been ongoing ever since an earlier occasion of communal dining (71–72), which actually led into the first song of Demodokos (73–83). And let me go even further back in time. Leading up to the communal dining, there had been an animal sacrifice (as expressed by the word hiereúein ‘sacrificially slaughter’: 59). Then, the meat of the sacrificed animals (twelve sheep, eight pigs, and two oxen: 59–60) had been prepared to be cooked at the feast (61). The word at line 61 for ‘feast’ is once again daís.
The noun dais ‘feast’ is derived from the verb daíesthai in the sense of ‘distribute’, which is used in contexts of animal sacrifice in referring to the ‘distribution’ of cooked meat among the members of a community (as in Odyssey 15.140 and 17.332). Then, by way of synecdoche, the specific idea of distribution extends metonymically to the general idea of feasting and further to the even more general idea of a festival. Following the logic of this sequence of meanings, we see that the animal sacrifice in Odyssey 8 (59) had led to the cooking and the distribution of the meat (61), which had led to the communal dining (71–72), which had led to the first song of Demodokos (73–83), and so on. In terms of this logic, the metonymic use of the word da í s ‘feast’ marks a whole complex of events that are typical of festivals: animal sacrifice, communal feasting, singing as well as dancing at the feast.”
Nagy, G. 2015. “The Metonymy of a Perfect Festive Moment.” Part 4 of Masterpieces of Metonymy: From Ancient Greek Times to Now. Washington, DC. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Masterpieces_of_Metonymy.2015.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Konnor Clark 2015.11.20 and Olga Levaniouk 2016.01.17
Ἐρύθεια (Erútheia)
Erútheia (Ἐρύθεια), ‘the Red one’, is a personal name, which is connected with the homonymous place name Erutheíā. This is an island located in the West and inhabited by Geryon and the Hesperides, as in Hesiod Theogony 289–290 τὸν μὲν ἄρ᾽ ἐξενάριξε βίη Ἡρακληείη / βουσὶ πάρ᾽ εἰλιπόδεσσι περιρρύτῳ εἰν Ἐρυθείῃ ‘Heracles’ force killed him (: Geryon) beside his rolling-footed cattle in sea-girt Erutheíē.’ The personal name Erútheia belongs to a marginal actor of the Sun-god’s travel:

Τότε δὴ χρυσέῳ ἐν δέπᾳ
Ἠέλιον πόμπεθεν ἀγακλυμένη Ἐρύθεια
‘Then the high-glorified Erytheia guided Helios in a golden cup’
(Antimachus F86 Matthews [= 66 Wyss])
Erútheia is connected to Geryon and, consequently, to the island Erutheíā in different ways. According to Pausania (Periegesis 10.17.5) Erútheia is Geryon’s daughter, while Apollodorus (Library 2.114.2) identifies her as one of the Hesperides, compare μετὰ τούτου δὲ Ἑσπερίδες ἐφύλαττον, Αἴγλη Ἐρύθεια Ἑσπερία Ἀρέθουσα ‘with it (: the dragon) the Hesperides also were on guard: Aiglē, Erútheia, Hespería, and Aréthousa.’
The association between Erútheia and Helios’ golden cup in Antimachus’ verses suggests that Erútheia is one of the Hesperides, the goddesses of the Evening. Indeed, the ‘golden dépas (cup)’ is a vehicle used by Helios during his nocturnal travel, as revealed by Mimnermus:

τὸν μὲν γὰρ διὰ κῦμα φέρει πολυήρατος εὐνή,
κοιΐλη, Ἡφαίστου χερσὶν ἐληλαμένη,
χρυσοῦ τιμήεντος, ὑπόπτερος, ἄκρον ἐφ’ ὕδωρ
εὕδονθ’ ἁρπαλέως χώρου ἀφ’ Ἑσπερίδων
γαῖαν ἐς Αἰθιόπων
‘A lovely bed, hollow, forged by the hands of Hephaestus, of precious gold and winged, carries him, as he sleeps soundly, over the waves on the water’s surface from the place of the Hesperides to the land of the Ethiopians
(Mimnermus fragment 12.5–9 Allen / West [7 Davies])
In the light of Mimnermus’ passage, it is likely that Erútheia, is one of the Evening goddesses, who guides or escorts Helios during the night, while he is sleeping in his golden dépas.
The mythological name has a transparent etymology. It is a feminine derivative to the Indo-European root *h1reudh- ‘to turn red; redden’, which underlies the adjective ‘red’ in several cognate languages, compare Greek eruthrós (ἐρυθρός), Latin ruber, Umbrian rufru, Tocharian A rtär, Tocharian B ratre, all reflecting a ro derivative to the same root.
The association between a female character associated with the Sun-god, the evening and the color red finds a striking parallel in the Baltic poetic tradition. Specifically, Latvian folksongs, the Dainas, tell us that the Sun-goddess Saule glows red every evening and wakes up in red the next day:

Latvian Daina 33791
Kālabad ik vakara / Gaisa gali atsārkuši? / Saule savus zīda svārkus / Ik vakara vēdināja
‘Why does the edge of the sky glow red every evening? The Sun airs her silk skirt every evening.’

Latvian Daina 33793
Kālabad šo rītiņu / Tik sarkana Saule lēce? / Vai tā bija rājusies / Ar Dieviņa māmuļīti?
‘Why has Saule woken up so red this morning? Did she quarrel with the Mother of God?’

A further Daina explicitly confirms that Saule turns red during the night:

Latvian Daina 33908
Saulīt’ bāla noiedama, / Atstāj laivu uz ūdeņa; / Rītā, sārta uzlēkdama, / Pārved laivu maliņā
‘Saule, pale when she goes to bed, leaves her boat on the water. In the morning, when she wakes up in red, she brings the boat ashore.’

Dainas may preserve a further link between the color red and the travel of the Sun-goddess. In one folksong, attested in the Latvian regions of Vidzeme, Kurzeme and Zemgale, Saule’s vehicle on the Daugava is pulled by a red fish :

Latvian Daina 33916
Saule brauca pār Daugavu / Laša kaula kamaņiņas / Asarītis zirgu dzina / Rauda tura kamaņiņas
‘Saule crossed the Daugava on a little sledge of salmon’s bones. The pole impelled the horse, the rauda (gardon/roach-fish) held the little sledge’

Significantly, the Latvian name of the red-fish, rauda, is an etymological congener of Erútheia, since it reflects a thematic derivative *h1roudho– ‘red’, also underlying Vedic lohá– ‘red metal’, Umbrian rofu, rofa, Gothic rauþs, Old Irish rúad ‘red.’

In conclusion: as a character, Erútheia is the red Evening goddess who helps the Sun-god Helios during his nocturnal travel. The association between the color red and an evening-goddess may reflect an Indo-European pattern, since in the Baltic tradition, the same color is associated with the nocturnal travel of the Sun.
Afanas’ev, A. N. 1865. Poetičeskie vozzreniya slavyan na prirodu. Tom 1. Moskva: Izd. Soldatenkova.
Massetti, L. 2019. “Antimachus’s Enigma: On Eruytheia, the Latvian Sun-goddess and a Red Fish.” The Journal of Indo-European Studies 47 1/2.223–240.
 
Laura Massetti 2021.04.15
Ἐρυσίχθων (Erusíkhthōn)
Erusíkhthōn (Ἐρυσίχθων) is the name of a prince who is afflicted with such an insatiable hunger that he turns into the famine demon Aíthōn (Αἴθων, ‘Mr. Burning’), compare Hesiod fragment 43a.2–6 Merkelbach-West Ἐρυσίχθονος […] τὸν δ’ Αἴθων’ ἐκάλεσσαν ἐπ]ών[υ]μ̣[ο]ν εἵνεκα λιμοῦ || αἴθωνος κρατεροῦ ‘of Erysichthon […] him they also called Aithon] by name because of his hunger, blazing strong.’ According to Callimachus’ Hymn to Demeter and Ovid’s Metamorphoses 8.728–778, Erusíkhthōn is guilty of cutting down the trees from the sacred grove of Demeter and is punished by the goddess with unrelenting appetite:

 

ᾄσθετο Δαμάτηρ, ὅτι οἱ ξύλον ἱερὸν ἄλγει,
εἶπε δὲ χωσαμένα “τίς μοι καλὰ δένδρεα κόπτει;” […]
αὐτίκα οἱ χαλεπόν τε καὶ ἄγριον ἔμβαλε λιμόν
αἴθωνα κρατερόν, μεγάλᾳ δ’ ἐστρεύγετο νούσῳ

 

Callimachus Hymn 6.40–41, 66–67
‘Demeter marked that her holy tree was in pain, and she was angered and said: – Who cuts down my fair trees? – Straightway she sent on him a cruel and evil hunger—a burning hunger and a strong—and he was tormented by a grievous disease’
From the formal point of view, Erusíkhthōn (Ἐρυσίχθων) reflects a compound with a first verbal member ἐρυσι°, belonging to the verb erúō (ἐρύω), ‘drag, draw, tear apart’, and a second member khthṓn (χθών), ‘earth’. Therefore, he is ‘the one who tears the earth apart’. The verb erúō (ἐρύω) has a vehement semantic component. In the Iliad and in the Odyssey, it commonly describes the vigorous dragging of ships to sea (Iliad 1.141+), or ashore (Odyssey 10.403+). Moreover, it applies to:

 

  • warriors dragging off dead bodies (nekrón, nekroús, see Iliad 5.573+) for plunder or ransom;
  • dogs and birds of prey dragging corpses and tearing them apart, e.g. Iliad 11.454 οἰωνοὶ ὠμησταὶ ἐρύουσι ‘but the birds that eat raw flesh will rend (you)’;
  • the violent dragging of someone by one of his/her body-parts, indicated in the genitive case, by means of a complement [ἐκ – body-partgen.] or an equivalent adverb, see, for instance, Odyssey 22.187–188 τὼ δ᾿ ἄρ᾿ ἐπαΐξανθ᾿ ἑλέτην ἔρυσάν τέ μιν εἴσω || κουρίξ “then the two of them sprung upon and seized him. They dragged him (: Melanthios) in by the hair”;
  • the vehement extraction of an object from a surface, e.g. Iliad 16.862–863 δόρυ χάλκεον ἐξ ὠτειλῆς || εἴρυσε λὰξ προσβάς “he drew the spear of bronze out of the wound, planting his heel (on the dead man)”
  • the ripping of a plant, e.g. Odyssey 10.302–303 ὣς ἄρα φωνήσας πόρε φάρμακον Ἀργεϊφόντης || ἐκ γαίης ἐρύσας “so saying, Argeïphontes gave me the herb, pulling it out of the ground.”

Remarkably, erusíkhthōn occurs as an epithet of a plowing animal in a fragment by the comic poet Straton (4th–3rd century BCE):

‘σὺ δ’ ἄρα θύεις ἐρυσίχθον’;’ οὐκ ἔφην ἐγώ
βοῦν δ’ εὐρυμέτωπον;’ ‘οὐ θύω βοῦν, ἄθλιε’

 

Straton fr. 1.19–20 Kock
‘Didn’t I say –You shall sacrifice an earth-drawing, broad-fronted ox? – I won’t sacrifice an ox, my dear–’
Indeed, plowing may be visualized as ‘cutting the earth’, as the use of Greek γῆν τέμνειν, γητομέω (‘earth-cut, i.e. plow’) shows, see, e.g. Solon fragment 13.47–48 West ἄλλος γῆν τέμνων πολυδένδρεον εἰς ἐνιαυτόν || λατρεύει “another one, cleaves the thickly wooded land and slaves away for a year.” It is probably not by chance that Lycophron, who calls the hero by his alias Aíthōn, describes him as γατομῶν* ‘earth-cutting, plowing’: Lycophron Alexandra 1395–1396 βούπειναν ἀλθαίνεσκεν ἀκμαίαν πατρός […] γατομοῦντος Αἴθωνος ‘(Mestra) assuaged the raging hunger of her fire, Aithon, who cuts the earth.’
At the same time, the ‘cutting down a (sacred) grove’ is imagined as a sort of violation or sexual abuse of the earth, since earth’s vegetation is commonly referred to as the hair of the Earth. In poetic contexts, κομάω ‘let hair grow long / wave the hair’ applies to the growth of trees and grass, compare Homeric Hymn 2.454 ταναοῖσι κομήσειν ἀσταχύεσσιν ‘(the ploughland) would come to wave the hair with long ears of corn.’ In a complementary way, ‘cutting the grass / the field / the vegetation’ is also a widespread sexual metaphor. Take, for instance, Pindar’s Pythian 9.36–37, in which Apollo asks Chiron for permission to have sex with young Cyrene: ὁσία […] ἐκ λεχέων κεῖραι μελιαδέα ποίαν; ‘is it right […] to reap the honey-sweet flower from the bed of love?’ Thus, on the one hand, Erusíkhthōn’s crime matches his name. On the other, the hero commits a major violation against Demeter, a goddess closely associated with Earth’s fertility, who consequently turns him into insatiable ‘Mr. Burning’ (Aíthōn, Αἴθων).
Significantly, in other Indo-European traditions, such as Old Indic and Old Norse, characters associated with the element ‘fire’ cause damage to Earth-goddesses or Earth-goddesses’ avatars and are punished in a way that affects their appetite.
Just as Erusíkhthōn is the name of the hero who cuts the woods (of Demeter) and the epithet of an ox (boûs, see above), in the Rigveda, the insatiable fire-god Agni is compared to the blade and to an ox:

 

ví vā́tajūto ataséṣu tiṣṭhate ‘ vŕ̥thā juhū́bhiḥ sŕ̥ṇyā tuviṣváṇiḥ
tr̥ṣú yád agne vaníno vr̥ṣāyáse ‘ kr̥ṣṇáṃ ta éma rúśadūrme ajara

 

Rigveda 1.58.4
“Sped by the wind, he spreads himself out among the thickets at will, with his tongues as sickle, powerfully noisy. When, Agni, thirstily you rush like a bull upon the woods, black is your course, o unaging one with gleaming waves.”
Agni is additionally said to shave the hair of the earth, Rigveda 1.65.8 yád vā́tajūto vánā víy ásthād / agnír ha dāti rómā pr̥thivyā́ḥ “when, sped by the wind, he has spread out through the wood, Agni cuts the hair of the earth”. Moreover, in a Sanskrit epic tale from the Mahābhārata (1.1.5–7), he accidentally causes damage to Pulomā, whose name is likely to reflect *pulu-loma(n)- ‘whose hair(s) is/are many’, with a first compound member pulu° standing for purú- ‘much, many’ (: Indo-European *pl̥h1-ú-) and a second member °lomā- related to Vedic róman- ‘hair’. As the Earth is the ‘hairy’ one also in the Old Indic tradition (compare Rigveda 8.91.6 asaú ca yā́ na urvárā […] tā́ romaśā́ kr̥dhi “that field of ours […] make all these hairy!”), the figure of Pulomā might be interpreted as a narrative avatar of the Earth-goddess. Not only does Agni’s offense resemble that of Erusíkhthōn against Demeter, but he is also punished in an analogous way. Bhr̥gu, Pulomā’s husband, condemns him to become insatiable, compare:

 

śaśāpāgnim abhikruddhaḥ     sarvabhakṣo bhaviṣyasi
Mahābhārata 1.1.6.13
“In a rage he (Bhr̥gu) cursed the Fire: – Thou shalt eat anything! –”
As properly underlined by Ginevra (2017), the main events and characters of the Sanskrit account may parallel those of an Old Norse story, namely: that of Loki’s offense against Sif.
Loki is a big-eater, who competes against the wild fire in appetite, compare Gylfaginning 46bd Hafði þá Loki etit slátr allt af beinum, en Logi hafði ok etit slátr allt ok beinin með ok svá trogit, ok sýndisk nú ǫllum sem Loki hefði látit leikinn “by that time Loki had eaten all the meat from the bones, but Logi [: the wild fire] likewise had eaten all the meat, and the bones with it, and the trough too; and now it seemed to all as if Loki had lost the game.” Like Erusíkhthōn and Agni, Loki damages a character associated with the element earth, by cutting her hair:

 

Loki Laufeyjarson hafði þat gert til lævísi at klippa hár alt af Sif
Skáldskaparmál 35
“Loki Laufeyiarson had done this for love of mischief: he had cut off all Sif’s hair
Sif is a heiti (i.e. a poetic designation) for the ‘Earth’ (Skáldskaparmál 75: Jǫrð … gyma, Sif earth […] (is) humus, Sif”), whose vegetation is referred to as ‘hair’ (haddr Iarðar ‘Eath’s hair’, Biarkamál fr. 7.1+), or ‘mane’ (Iarðar fax, ‘Earth’s mane’, Snjólfr 5.14) in the skaldic poetry. After mutilating Sif, Loki looses his head in a competition against Brokkr, a skillful smith, and is punished by having his mouth sewn together, which may ultimately represent a sort of restraint on his mouth.
To sum up: Erusíkhthōn is the hero ‘who tears the Earth apart’, whose crime—cutting a sacred grove of Demeter—matches his name. In a similar way as he becomes ‘Mr. Burning’ (Aíthōn) in connection with this event, characters associated with ‘fire’ in other Indo-European languages (Sanskrit Agni and Old Norse Loki) cause damage to characters associated with the element ‘earth’ (Sanskrit Pulomā, Old Norse Sif). Furthermore, they are punished in a way which affects their appetite. In this regard, the insatiable appetite of Agni in Mahābhārata 1.1.6.13 is strikingly reminiscent of that of Erusíkhthōn/Aíthōn, who suffers of burning hunger.
Ginevra, Riccardo. 2017. “Old Norse Brokkr, Sanskrit Bhr̥gu and PIE *(s)bhr̥(h2)g ‘crackle, roar’*.” In Proceedings of the 28th Annual UCLA Indo-European Conference (Los Angeles, 11–12.11.2016), eds. David M. Goldstein, Stephanie W. Jamison, Brent Vine, 1–22. Bremen.
Levaniouk, O. 2000. “Aithôn, Aithon and Odysseus.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 100:25–51.
Massetti, L. In preparation. “Erysichthon’s Crime and Punishment: the Prehistory of a Famine Demon.”
 
Laura Massetti 2019.04.03
ἑστία (hestíā)
The symbolism of the hestíā ‘hearth’ as the generatrix of authority and kingship is envisioned by Clytemnestra’s dream in the Electra of Sophocles: she dreams the Agamemnon comes back from the dead and plants his scepter in the family hearth. From the hearth, there grows out of the scepter a shoot so vigorous that it covers with its shade all the kingdom of Mycenae (417–423).
This symbolism of the Greek hestíā ‘hearth’ as the generatrix of authority is a matter of Indo-European heritage. Turning to the evidence of other Indo-European languages, specifically the hieratic diction of such disparate organizations as the Atiedian Brethren of Umbrian Iguvium and the Brahmans of the Indic Vedas, we find some striking convergences with the Greek model. Such convergences are likely to represent the actual traces of cognate religious attitudes, or even of cognate institutions.
According to Georges Dumézil, the root *wes– of Greek hestíā ‘hearth’ (ἑστία) and Latin Vesta, Roman goddess of the hearth, has a cognate in the Indic form vi-vás-vat-. The mythical figure Vivasvat (vi-vás-vat-), is the first person ever to receive fire on earth, by virtue of being the first sacrificer on earth; he is ipso facto the ancestor of the human race. In Vedic diction, to say sádane vivásvataḥ ‘at the place of the Vivasvat’ (Rig-Veda 1.53.1, etc.) is the same as saying ‘at the sacrifice’. The root of this Indic verb vas– is cognate with the root *wes– of Greek hestíā ‘hearth’ (ἑστία) and of Latin Vesta, Roman goddess of the hearth.” There is a further possibility that root *wes– of Greek hestíā could be reconstructed further as *h2wes-, and that this root *h2wes– is a variant of *h2es-.
As a verb, *h2es– must have meant something like ‘set on fire’—or so we might infer from the comparative evidence of various Indo-European languages. Purely on phonological grounds, we may expect the root *h2es– to survive in the Hittite language as ḫaš-, and there is indeed an attested Hittite noun ḫašša– meaning ‘sacrificial fireplace’. This noun, it is generally agreed, is related in form to Latin āra ‘sacrificial fireplace, altar’. There is also a Hittite verb ḫaš– meaning not ‘set on fire’ but ‘beget’. Despite this semantic anomaly, this Hittite verb ḫaš– ‘beget’ may be related to the noun ḫašša– ‘sacrificial fireplace’. The actual context for a semantic relationship between the concepts of “beget” and “fireplace” may be latent in the heritage of myth and ritual. There is a related problem in the semantics of the Hittite noun ḫaššu-, meaning ‘king’, which has been connected in some studies with the verb ḫaš– ‘beget’. Both this noun and ḫašša– ‘sacrificial fireplace’ are derived from the same Hittite verb has– ‘beget’.
Going beyond Dumézil’s position, the root *wes– could be reconstructed further as *h2wes-, despite the absence of any phonological trace of word-initial *h2 before *w in Greek *westiā, whence hestíā ‘hearth’ (ἑστία). Is this reconstruction turns out to be valid, then the root *h2wes– of the Greek noun hestíā ‘hearth’ may possibly be interpreted as a variant of the root *h2es– as in the Hittite noun ḫašša– ‘hearth’—and in the Hittite verb ḫaš– ‘beget’. Such a root-variation *h2es– vs. *h2wes– would be in line with an Indo-European pattern attested in a series of possible examples shaped CeC(C)- vs. Cu̯eC(C)-. Given that Indic vas– ‘shine’ conveys simultaneously the themes of the shining sun, the kindling of sacrificial fire, and the begetting of progeny, the reconstruction *h2wes– of this root would make it a formal variant of *h2es-, as in Hittite ḫaš– ‘beget’ and ḫašša– ‘sacrificial fireplace’.
The Indic verb vas– ‘shine’, tentatively reconstructed as *h2wes-, has a noun-derivative uṣás– ‘dawn’, which in turn can be reconstructed as *h2usos-. There is an e-grade variant, h2eusos-, attested in Latin aurōra ‘dawn’ and in Greek aúōs/ēṓs (Aeolic αὔως/ Ionic ἠώς) ‘dawn’. According to this scheme, there is a possibility that both Latin and Greek have words for the macrocosm of ‘dawn’ built from the root *h2ews– and for the microcosm of ‘sacrificial fireplace’ built from the same root, but with a different configuration: *h2wes– as in Greek, hestíā (ἐστία) and Latin Vesta.
In addition to the linking of the hearth with the ideas of generation and kingship, there is, then, an Indo-European pattern of thought that links the rising of the sun at dawn as parallel to the kindling of the sacrificial fire. This parallelism is explicit in the ritual language of the Vedas and it is implicit in the possible affinity between Indo-European roots in words for ‘dawn’, notably Greek ēṓs and Latin aurōra, and in words for ‘hearth’, notably Greek hestíā and Latin Vesta. In other words, the possibility remains that the macrocosm of dawn and the microcosm of sacrificial fire are designated with variants of the same root, with *hews– for ‘dawn’ and *hwes– for ‘fireplace’.
Nagy, G. 1990. “The King and the Hearth: Six Studies of Sacral Vocabulary relating to the Fireplace.” Chapter 6 of Greek Mythology and Poetics. Ithaca, NY. nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Greek_Mythology_and_Poetics.1990.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Fana Yirga, 2015.12.10 and Olga Levaniouk 2016.01.18.

Εὐρύφάεσσα (Eurupháessa)

According to an isolated tradition, Eurupháessa (Εὐρυφάεσσα) is the name of the mother of Helios (Sun), Selene (Moon), and Eos (Dawn):

 

γῆμε γὰρ Εὐρυφάεσσαν ἀγακλειτὴν Ὑπερίων,
αὐτοκασιγνήτην, ἥ οἱ τέκε κάλλιμα τέκνα,
Ἠῶ τε οδόπηχυν ἐυπλόκαμόν τε Σελήνην
Ἠέλιόν τ᾽ ἀκάμαντ᾽(α) […]
“For Hyperion married the famed Eurupháessa, his own sister, who bore him fine children: rose-armed Eos (Dawn), lovely-tressed Selene (Moon), and tireless Helios (Sun)” (Homeric Hymn 31.4–7)
The theonym is a compound with the meaning ‘widely-shining’. The first compound member is the adjective εὐρύς ‘wide, broad’, which can be transposed as *(h1?)urHú-, and parallels, among others, Vedic urú- ‘wide, broad’, Tocharian A wärts, Tocharian B wartse ‘broad’. The second member, °φάεσσα ‘shining’, belongs to the same Indo-European root as Greek φαίνω ‘to shine’, namely: Indo-European *bheh2 ‘shine’ and it is best analyzed as a feminine active participle, proceeding from Indo-European *bheh2-n̥t-ih2. The expected outcome *phāssa-, from *phānti̯a-, may have been remodeled into °φάεσσα, by analogy with the productive Greek adjective type χαρίεις, χαρίεσσα, χαρίεν (‘graceful’).
As Enrico Campanile (1987) pointed out, Eurupháessa is an avatar of the Indo-European Dawn-Goddess. Indeed, she shares a number of specific features with the Vedic Dawn-Goddess Uṣas. To begin with, Uṣas is often described through the epithet vibhātī́-, ‘widely shining’, which displays the adverb vi° ‘away’ as a first member, and a second member °bhātī́-, reflecting *bheh2-n̥t-ih2, a feminine participle to the Vedic root bhā ‘to shine’, compare Greek φαίνω. The Vedic epithet is often combined with the adverbial form urviyā́– ‘widely’, which is etymologically related to Greek εὐρύς, compare:

 

víśvāni devī́ bhúvanābhicákṣyā
pratīcī́ cákṣur urviyā́ ví bhāti
“The goddess, overseeing all creatures, (like) an eye, facing toward them, shines forth widely” (Rigveda 1.92.9ab)
Moreover, like Eurupháessa ‘wide-shining’, U ṣas is the mother of the Vedic Sun-god:

 

etā́ u tyā́ḥ práty adr̥śran purástāj
jyótir yáchantīr uṣáso vibhātī́ḥ
ájījanan sū́riyaṃ yajñám agním
apācī́naṃ támo agād ájuṣṭam
“These very dawns have been seen opposite in the east, extending their light, radiating widely. They have generated the sun, the sacrifice, the fire. The disagreeable darkness has gone back behind” (Rigveda 7.78.3)
On the basis of Homeric Hymn 31.1–3 it is possible to reconstruct a collocation ‘the Widely-Shining One generated the Sun’, compare ἥλιον […] φαέθοντα, τὸν Εὐρυφάεσσα βοῶπις / γείνατο “Of Helios, […] the shining one, whom mild-eyed Euruphaessa bore.” The entire collocation constitutes a threefold partial match to Vedic vibhātī́ḥ ájījanan sū́riyam (Rigveda 7.78.3bc)
Eurupháessa (Εὐρυφάεσσα) partially matches Vedic vibhātī́- ‘radiating’;
Greek γείνατο and Vedic ájījanan go back to the same Indo-European root *ĝenh1 ‘to generate’;
Greek ἥλιος is etymologically related to Vedic sū́riyam ‘sun’. These terms can be respectively traced back to *seh2u̯li̯o- (Greek ἥλιος) and *súh2li̯o- (Vedic sū́riya-).
In conclusion, it is likely that Eurupháessa reflects an epithet of the Indo-European Dawn-Goddess, which came to designate the mother of the Sun-god.
Campanile, E. 1987. “Histoire et préhistoire d’une formule poétique indo-européennes.” In Georges Dumézil in memoriam, ed. Jean-Paul Allard, 21–24. Lyon: Institut d’études indo-européennes.
Massetti, L. In print. “Once upon a time a *Sleeping Beauty … Indo-European Parallel to Sole, Luna e Talia (Giambattista Basile Pentamerone 5.5).” AION N.S. 20.
 
Laura Massetti 2019.08.14
Ἠριδανός (Ēridanós)
Ēridanós (Ἠριδανός) is the name of a river-god, son of Okeanos and Tethys (compare Hesiod Theogony 338) (→ Ōkeanós and → Tēthus). Ancient sources differ on where the water stream of Ēridanós is located: Aeschylus (Tragicorum Graecorum Fragmenta III 73) identifies the river with the Rhone and thus situates it in Spain; Euripides (Hippolytus 736–737) states that the Ēridanós empties into the Gulf of Venice and thus corresponds to the river Po; Herodotus (3.115) contends that the Ēridanós is a mythical river and does not actually exist.
As Gregory Nagy (1990:237) points out, Ēridanós is thematically parallel to his mythological father Okeanos: just like Okeanos (compare Hesiod Theogony 133), Ēridanós is said to be bathudínēs ‘deep-eddying’ (Hesiod Theogony 338). Moreover, according to Aeschylus (Tragicorum Graecorum Fragmenta III 73), the daughters of the Sun turned into poplars on the banks of Ēridanós. The same plants are said to grow on Okeanos’ banks in Odyssey 10.508–512. Furthermore, both Okeanos and Ēridanós are imagined as rivers which join the world and the netherworld. Finally, the description of the ‘fall’ (Greek épesen , Iliad 8.458) of the sun-light into Okeanos verbally resembles the representation of Phaethon’s fall into Ēridanós. The mythological analogy between Okeanos and Ēridanós is mirrored at a genealogical level: Okeanos is the father of Ēridanós, while Helios is Phaethon’s father.
The synchronic etymology of Ēridanós connected it to Greek verb δαίω (daíō) and, probably, the adjective δᾱνός (dānós) ‘dry, burnt’, derivatives of Indo-European * deh2– to burn. This intuitive linguistic connection underlies a passage by Nonnos of Panopolis:

ἀλλὰ τεῶν ὑδάτων ἔτι φείδεο μηδὲ νοήσω
Ἠριδανῷ φλεχθέντι κεκαυμένον ἶσον Ὑδάσπην

Dionysiaca 23.250–251
‘(But pray) I may spare your waters awhile, or I may see you, Hydaspes, burnt up in fiery flames like Eridanos

However, Ēridanós displays a short – a – and it is not likely to contain dānós ‘dry’.

The interpretation of the river’s name is debated. Kretschmer (1937:207–210) proposed to connect ēri– with the term ἠρίον (ēríon) ‘hill’. Differently, Pokorny (1969:193–197) proposed that the name was an adapted borrowing from *Rhodanos, through an Iberic mediation *Errodanos, which was ‘Hellenized’ as Ēridanós.

As suggested by Nagy (1990:246) it is rather likely that the name is a compound. Accordingly, it displays a first member ēri-, i.e a locative form from *h2eu̯s-er-i ‘at dawn’ meaning ‘early’, compare Greek ἦρι (êri) ‘early’. The second compound member –danós is etymologically related to the basis *da-, Indo-European *deh2-, which is featured in several river names, like Scythian Tanais, Irish Danu, Welsh Don, Lithuanian Dunōjus, Latvian Duņavas, Germanic Danube. As further suggested by Janda (2002:256–8) and Nikolaev (2019) *deh2– may underlie the goddess name Daeîra (→ Daeîra) and the god’s name Poseidon (Poseidáōn), which might ultimately result from the univerbation of a vocative ‘O Lord of the Waters!’. Accordingly, the semantics of the name would reflect ‘Early watery’*. As Nagy (1990:246) explains: “Since Okeanos is thematically parallel with Eridanos, the sunset theme of a dead Phaethon falling into Eridanos implies an inverse sunrise theme of a reborn Phaethon emerging from Eridanos.” We may conclude that the river stands as a symbol of rebirth.
The mythological background of Ēridanós thus supports the interpretation of the name as ‘Early-watery’.
Janda, M. Eleusis: das indogermanische Erbe der Mysterien. Innsbruck: Institut für Sprachwissenschaft der Universität Innsbruck.
Kretschmer, P. Eridanos. 1937. J. van Ginneken (ed.): Mélanges de linguistique et de philologie offerts à Jacq. Van Ginneken à l’occasion du soixantième anniversaire de sa naissance (21 avril 1937), 207–210. Paris: Klincksieck.
Nagy, G. 1990. Greek Mythology and Poetics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Nikolaev, A. 2019. “ΔΑΕΙΡΑ, the lady of the waters.” In: Nikolai Kazanski (ed.): Indo-European Linguistics and Classical Philology XXIII. Proceedings of the 23rd Conference in Memory of Professor Joseph M. Tronsky, June 24–26, 2019, 790–795. Saint Petersburg: Nauka.
Pokorny, M. J. 1969. Eridanos et Rhodanus. In: Mélanges Émile Boisacq (= Annuaire de l’Institut de philology et d’histoire orientales et slaves 6), 2.193–197.
 
Laura Massetti 2021.10.27
῾Ησίοδος (Hēsíodos)
The name of Hesiod is announced in the Hesiodic Theogony (22): it is Hēsíodos (Ἡσίοδος). I interpret the etymology of this name as *hēsíwodos, meaning ‘he who emits the voice’. The first part of this compound formation *hēsíwodos comes from the root of the verb hiénai (ἱέναι) ‘emit’, while the second part comes from the root of the noun audḗ (αὐδή) ‘voice’. And the Muses literally ‘breathe’ (pneîn) into him an audḗ ’voice’ that makes him a poet (31 ἐνέπνευσαν δέ μοι αὐδήν). This poetic voice is his inspiration. There is a semantic correspondence between this etymology of *hēsíwodos meaning ‘he who emits the voice’ and the description of the singing Muses as ὄσσαν ἱεῖσαι ‘emitting the voice’ (Theogony 10, 43, 65, 67), which applies to these goddesses in descriptions of their singing and dancing (7–8, 63).
Nagy, Gregory. 2009. “Hesiod and the Ancient Biographical Traditions.” The Brill Companion to Hesiod, ed. F. Montanari, A. Rengakos, and Ch. Tsagalis, 287–288. Leiden. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.essay:Nagy.Hesiod_and_the_Ancient_Biographical_Traditions.2009.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Edgar A. García 2015.11.03
Ἴθας or Ἴθαξ (Ithas or Ithax)
According a gloss collected in the corpus of the ancient lexicographer Hesychius, Ithas (Ἴθας) or Ithax (Ἴθαξ) is the herald of the Titans, that is to say, Prometheus: Ἴθας· ὁ τῶν Τιτήνων κῆρυξ. Προμηθεύς. τινὲς Ἴθαξ (Hesychius ι 387 L) “Ithas: the herald of the Titans. Prometheus. Some (say) Ithax.”
Both Ithas and Ithax can be traced back to a Proto-Indo-European root *h2ei̯dh- ‘kindle’ (Latte 1966:354, Morani 1983:42). In the light of the Hittite cognate verbs aāri ‘is warm’, inuzi ‘makes warm’, which show no trace of an initial laryngeal two, the Indo-European root for ‘produce warmth, kindle’ can be reconstructed as *h1ai̯dh-.
Specifically, Ithas could reflect a type Thóas, -antos (proper name, related to Greek thoós ‘swift’) or a type phugás, -ádos ‘fugitive’ with accent shift. In both cases, the form Ithas may ultimately be based on a thematic unattested stem *ithós. On the other side, a name Ithax could exist beside a feminine ithḗ ‘*warmth/heat’ (compare Hesychius ι 392 L ἰθή· εὐφροσύνη “ithḗ: mirth”), and count as a further example of the Greek synchronic pattern for names like pîdax (πῖδαξ) ‘water spring’ and sálax (σάλαξ) ‘sieve’ described by Kölligan (2017). According to this pattern, an –ak-form pairs with a feminine stem, for instance pîdax ‘water-spring’ beside pidḗ (πιδή*) ‘water-spring’, which might lie at the basis of the adjective pidḗeis (πιδήεις) ‘rich in springs’. A possible meaning for both Ithas and Ithax would then be ‘the one who produces warmth, the one who kindles (the fire)’.
The role of ‘fire-lighter’ perfectly suits Prometheus, the Titan who delivered fire to the human race (Hesiod Theogony 561–570, Works and Days 48–58). Consequently, according to Diodorus Siculus, Prometheus invented the pūreîa (fire-lighters): Ἰαπετοῦ δὲ Προμηθέα […] πρὸς δ᾽ ἀλήθειαν εὑρετὴν γενόμενον τῶν πυρείων, ἐξ ὧν ἐκκάεται τὸ πῦρ (Diodorus Siculus Library 5.67.2 ) “and to Iapetus was born Prometheus […] the truth is that he was the discoverer of fire-sticks, from which fire is kindled”.
The link between Prometheus and the role ‘herald’, however, can be only tentatively reconstructed within the Greek tradition, where it is very scarcely documented. A possible starting point could be the comparison between the action of ‘carrying fire’ and that of ‘carrying messages’. Pausanias (Description of Greece 1.30.2) reports that Prometheus was worshipped through torch races in Athens. The athletic gesture of ‘carrying fire’ is equated to that of ‘carrying a message’ by Greek literary sources of the Classical Age (for example, Herodotus Histories 8.98.1–2, Aeschylus Agamemnon 281–316) and by Hyginus (Astronomica 2.15.1.5–15).
The comparative data pertaining to the Vedic myth of the fire-theft cast new light on the figure of Ithas, who shares a set of characteristics with the Vedic fire-thief, namely:

 

(a) ‘Stealing fire’: It has long be recognized (Narten 1960:) that Vedic math describes Mātariśvan’s endeavor in the Vedic hymns such as Rigveda 1.148.1a máthīd yád īṃ viṣṭó mātaríśvā “since with effort Mātariśvan stole him (: Agni)”. Indo-European *math ‘steal, rob’ underlies both Vedic math and the personal name Prometheus, which should be regarded as *Pro-māth-eus, that is to say, as compounded form containing the long-grade of the same Proto-Indo-European root math.
(b) ‘Kindling fire’: Like Prometheus, Mātariśvan kindles fire, for instance in Rigveda 3.5.10cd yádī bhŕ̥gubhyaḥ pári mātaríśvā ‘ gúhā sántaṃ havyavā́haṃ samīdhé “when Mātariśvan kindled him [: Agni] hiding from the Bhr̥gus, conveying the oblation.” The Vedic verb sam-idh- ‘kindle’ goes back to Proto-Indo-European *h1ai̯dh- ‘kindle’, which lies at the basis of Ithas. Additionally, it is remarkable that the Vedic root noun samídh- ‘kindling’ often denotes the ‘kindling stick’, as in Rigveda 10.51.2cd kuvā́ha mitrāvaruṇā kṣiyantiy ‘ agnér víśvāḥ samídho devayā́nīḥ “where indeed, o Mitra and Varuṇa, are all the kindling sticks of Agni lying, which lead to the gods?”
(c) ‘Carrying messages’: Mātariśvan is sometimes identified with the Vedic fire-god, Agni, who is the messenger of the gods: Rigveda 3.5.9 úd u ṣṭutáḥ samídhā yahvó adyaud ‘ várṣman divó ádhi nā́bhā pr̥thivyā́ḥ / mitró agnír ī́ḍiyo mātaríśvā ‘ ā́ dūtó vakṣad yajáthāya devā́n “praised, the young one has flared up through his kindling upon the summit of heaven and the navel of earth. To be invoked as Mitra and Mātariśvan, Agni as a messenger will convey the gods to the sacrifice.” As the passage suggests, Agni can move towards the sky thanks to kindling (samídhā, instrumental of the root noun samídh-, see above). In this fashion, he becomes the messenger of the gods. Even when Mātariśvan and Agni are regarded as two distinct figures, the importance of Mātariśvan is closely connected with Agni as the ‘messenger of the gods’, compare Rigveda 1.71.4 máthīd yád īṃ víbhr̥to mātaríśvā ‘ gr̥hé-gr̥he śyetó jényo bhū́t / ā́d īṃ rā́jñe ná sáhīyase sácā sánn ‘ ā́ dūtíyàm bhŕ̥gavāṇo vivāyawhen Mātariśvan, borne away, stole him, and he of worthy birth came to be gleaming in every house, after that (the fire) of the Bhr̥gus undertook the role of messenger, as if for a more powerful king, being associated with him.”
We can conclude: the name Ithas or Ithax may be interpreted a ‘the one who produces warmth / kindles fire’ while its bearer is identified as Prometheus in a Hesychian gloss. Prometheus steals fire and bestows it to the human race. Therefore, he is also the inventor of the fire-sticks. In the same gloss, Ithas / Ithax is also identified as the messenger of the Titans (Ἴθας· ὁ τῶν Τιτήνων κῆρυξ. Προμηθεύς. τινὲς Ἴθαξ “Ithas: the herald of the Titans. Prometheus. Some (say) Ithax,” Hesychius ι 387 L). The missing links between Ithas / Ithax, Prometheus, and the function ‘messenger’ can be very clearly reconstructed by taking into account the phraseological comparison between the Greek and the Vedic fire-theft episode. Here, Mātariśvan ‘steals fire’ (Vedic math), ‘kindles’ it (Vedic sam-idh), and is sporadically identified with Agni, the messenger (Vedic dūtá-) of the gods par excellence.
Jamison, Stephanie W., and Joel P. Brereton, trans. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. 3 Vols. Oxford.
Kölligan, D. 2016. “Trois noms grecs en -ak-: πῖδαξ, λῦμαξ, φύλαξ.” Nouveaux acquis sur la formation des noms en grec ancien : actes du colloque international, Université de Rouen, ERIAC, 17-18 octobre 2013, eds. A. Blanc and D. Petit, 117–133. Louvain.
———. 2017. “Gr. σάλαξ, σκύθραξ und die griechischen Nomina auf –ak-.” Miscellanea indogermanica. Festschrift für José Luis García Ramón zum 65. Geburtstag, eds. I. Hajnal, D. Kölligan, and K. Zipster, 369–82. Innsbruck.
Latte, K., ed. 1966. Hesychii Alexandrini Lexicon. Vol. 2, E-X. Haunia / Copenhagen.
Massetti, L. (In print). “Another avatar of Mātariśvan?” Proceedings of the 29th UCLA Indo-European Conference, eds. D. Goldstein, S. Jamison, and B. Vine. Bremen.
Morani, M. 1983. “Il nome di Prometeo.” Aevum 57.1:33–43.
Narten, J. 1960. “Das vedische Verbum math.” Indo-Iranian Journal 4:121–135.
 
Laura Massetti 2018.08.29
Ἶρις (Îris)
Îris (Ἶρις) is the name of the messenger of the gods and the rainbow in the epics (as in ἠΰτε πορφυρέην ἶριν θνητοῖσι τανύσσῃ / Ζεύς ἐξ οὐρανόθεν, ‘as Zeus stretches for mortals a dark-shimmering rainbow out of heaven’, Iliad 17.546–547).
The name displays an initial digamma in Greek, [W]îris ([Ϝ]ἶρις). It has long been interpreted as an individualizing i-stem built on a ro-adjective to the Indo-European root *u̯ieh1 ‘to wrap, envelop, turn’ (compare Latin viēre ‘to bend, twist’). In this scenario, the ro-adjectives and substantives meaning ‘wire’, Old English wīr, Old Norse vīrr, and Welsh gŵyr ‘bent’ would be the closest linguistic relatives of the name (DELG under Ἶρις, Weiss 1996: 204–205). Moreover, the semantics of the Greek word for ‘rainbow’ as something ‘enwrapping, curved’ would parallel that of ‘rainbow’ in Latin arcus and Old Norse regnbogi. This explanation perfectly fits îris ‘rainbow’ as a physical phenomenon, but is less suitable for Îris as the messenger of the gods.
As recently underlined by G. Nagy 2017 (on Iliad 17.547–549, Odyssey 18.006–007), it is possible to connect Îris to the Indo-European root *u̯ei̯h1 ‘to be eager, strive’ or ‘to have fresh energy’, which lies at the base of the adjectival form *u̯ih1-ro-. This form is continued by Tocharian A wir ‘young’, and several substantives meaning ‘man, hero’ in a variety of Indo-European languages, such as Vedic vīrá– ‘young man’, Avestan vīra– ‘young man’, Latin vir ‘man’. The ro-adjective also underlies the personal name Îros (Ἶρος). Îros, the Ithacan beggar who fights against Odysseus in Odyssey 18, is so called by the young men because like the messenger goddess Îris, ‘he used to run on errands when anyone bade him’ (Ἶρον δὲ νέοι κίκλησκον ἅπαντες, / οὕνεκ᾽ ἀπαγγέλλεσκε κιών, ὅτε πού τις ἀνώγοι, Odyssey 18.6–7). Additionally, several word-plays in the episode make reference to the diachronical etymology of the name (see, for example, ἦ τάχα Ἶρος ἄϊρος ἐπίσπαστον κακὸν ἕξει, ‘soon now shall Iros, un-Irosed (literally ‘Îros deprived of strength’), have a trouble of his own creation’, Odyssey 18.73, in which the adjective ἄϊρος perfectly matches Vedic avīrá– ‘powerless’).
Being the messenger of the gods, Îris is characterized by ‘fresh energy’, which commonly manifests itself as swiftness. For instance, in Hesiod Theogony 266–269, she is mentioned as the sister of the swift-flying harpies, and in fragment 327 V of Alcaeus, she mingles with the wind-god Zephyros. In the Iliad she is described as takheîa ‘swift’ (ταχεῖα, Iliad 8.399), pod ḗnemos ōkéa ‘wind-footed’ (ποδήνεμος ὠκέα, Iliad 2.786), aellópos ‘storm-footed’ (ἀελλόπος, Iliad 8.409), or as the ‘golden-winged messenger’ (χρυσόπτερον ἀγγελέουσαν, Iliad 8.399).
If Îris goes back to a root *u̯ei̯h1 ‘to be eager, strive’, her name is etymologically related to a Vedic personal and divine name Vena (Vená– ‘Seeker’, reflecting *u̯ei̯h1-nó-, compare vená– ‘tracker’ RV 1.83.5b+). In the only hymn dedicated to this divine figure (Rigveda 10.123), Vena’s description matches that of Îris in several respects. Like Îris, Vena

 

(a) is the golden-winged messenger of the gods (híraṇyapakṣam váruṇasya dūtám, ‘the golden-winged messenger of Varuṇa,’ Rigveda 10.123.6cd);
(b) flies and is directly compared to a bird of prey, (nā́ke suparṇám úpa yát pátantaṃ, ‘you, an eagle flying to the vault’, Rigveda 10.123.6b);
(c) is possibly identified with the rainbow, as proposed by Oldenberg (1912: 341–342). Vena, the ‘Seeker’, is generated from the union of water and light (imám apā́ṃ saṃgamé sū́ryasya, ‘this one [they lick] at the union of the waters and the sun’, Rigveda 10.123.1c), and is ‘born from the cloud’ (nabhojā́ḥ pr̥ṣṭháṃ haryatásya darśi, ‘the cloud-born one, the top of the delightful one has been sighted’, Rigveda 10.123.1b). The latter verse strikingly resembles one Greek passage about Îris in a fragment of Xenocrates: ἥν τ’ Ἶριν καλέουσι, νέφος […] πέφυκε || πορφύρεον καὶ φοινίκεον καὶ χλωρὸν ἰδέσθαι, ‘that which they call Iris is by nature the cloud, and purple, red and yellow to see’ (28.1–2 D).
In conclusion, Îris, the messenger of the gods and the personified rainbow, can be formally explained as an individualizing i-stem, built on a ro-adjective, namely (i) *u̯ih1-ro-, belonging to *u̯ieh1 ‘to wrap, envelop, turn’ (compare Old English wīr ‘wire’), or (ii) *u̯ih1-ro-, belonging to *u̯ei̯h1 ‘to be eager, strive’ / ‘to have fresh energy’ (compare Latin vir ‘man’). The latter etymology can be supported by some phraseological data: Îris is swift-flying and golden-winged like her putative Vedic counterpart Vená– (*u̯ei̯h1-nó-), who is possibly identified with the rainbow in the Rigveda.
DELG = Chantraine, P. 1968–1980. Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque: histoire des mots. Paris.
Massetti, L. 2016. “Two Lovely Names: On Κύπρις and Ἶρις.” Münchener Studien zur Sprachwissenschaft 70/1:41–60.
Nagy, G. 2017. “A sampling of comments on the Iliad and Odyssey.” http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.essay:Nagy.A_Sampling_of_Comments_on_the_Iliad_and_Odyssey.2017.
Oldenberg, H. 1912. gveda. Textkritische und exegetische Noten. 2. Siebentes bis zehntes Buch. Berlin.
Weiss, M. 1996. “Greek μυρίος ‘countless’, Hittite mūri- ‘bunch (of fruit)’.” Historische Sprachforschung 109/1-2: 199–278.
 
Laura Massetti 18.07.21
Κάστωρ (Kástōr)
Kástōr (Κάστωρ) is a personal and mythological name, which is first attested in Mycenaean as ka-to /Kastōr/ (KN Dv 1169, on which compare García Ramón 1988, 1992). In hexameter poetry, Kástōr is the name of the twin (half)-brother of Poludeúkēs (Πολυδεύκης, → Poludeúkēs). As a pair, Kástōr and Poludeúkēs are commonly identified as the Dióskouroi or Tundarídai, i.e. as the sons Leda bore to Zeus and the Spartan king Tyndareos, compare

Τυνδαρίδας, Λήδης καλλισφύρου ἀγλαὰ τέκνα,
Κάστορά θ᾽ ἱππόδαμον καὶ ἀμώμητον Πολυδεύκεα

Homeric Hymn 33.2–3
The Tyndarids, splendid sons of Lēdē of beautiful ankles:
Kastōr, tamer of horses and blameless Poludeúkēs.

According to the myth (compare, for example, [Apollodorus] Library 3.10.7), Tyndareos is Kástōr’s father, while Zeus is Poludeúkēs’ father. This myth may have parallels in Old Indic (Frame 2009:62–76 and Pirart 1995) As explained by Nagy (2013, 0§5), since immortality is ‘a recessive gene’ in Greek mythology, “the absolute mortality of Castor is symmetrically counterbalanced by [the] absolute immortality [of Pollux]” (Nagy 2016, with my addenda or changes between square brackets). That is, if Pollux had been the only child of Zeus and Leda, the combination of a mortal woman with an immortal god would have resulted in Pollux being a mortal. However, Kástōr and Poludeúkēs are born as twins and manage to recombine their absolute (im)mortality components. After Kástōr is killed in a fight against Idas and Lynkeus, a rival pair of twins from Messenia (compare Pindar, Nemean Ten), Poludeúkēs makes a mystical deal with Zeus. Accordingly, both Kástōr and Poludeúkēs become half immortal and half mortal, but count as dominantly immortal as a pair.

Remarkably, the cosmological visualizations of the Dioskouroi imagine them as coexisting in alternating times and places, as when they represent the Morning and the Evening Star, Lucifer and Hesperus (compare Nagy 1990:258–259, Frame 2009: 74–84).
In this connection, it is significant that the cosmological dimension of the Greek Dióskouroi matches that of the Vedic and Baltic Divine Twins (Mannhardt 1857). The characteristics and myths of the Vedic Aśvins/Nāsatyas (see → Néstōr), the Lithuanian Diẽvo sunẽliai, and the Latvian Dieva dēli also mythologize the cosmological functions of the Morning and Evening Star, the (alternating) escorts of the Sun by day and night (compare Gotō 2009 on the Vedic twins). Indeed, within the three Indo-European traditions the Divine Twins are related or connected with Sun-deities or characters associated with the sun: the Dioskouroi are brothers of Helen, who is commonly thought to have inherited some features belonging to the Indo-European Sun-Maiden (Jackson 2006, see → Diòs thugáthēr); the Aśvins/Nāsatyas woo or marry the Sun-Maiden Sūryā; the Baltic ‘Sons of God’ rescue the Sun-goddess Saule or are the groomsmen of the Sun-Maiden.
Names and attributes of the Divine Twins in Greek, Vedic, and Baltic are also the same: the twin gods are young, splendid, and extremely mobile. They are indeed associated with ‘horses’, ‘boats’ and ‘chariots’ (compare Ginevra (forthc.) with reference to an Old Norse comparandum). The juncture ‘Kástōr tamer of horses’ (Kástora th’ hippódamon, see above) thus perfectly aligns with the standard traits of the Indo-European Divine Twins.
From the etymological point of view, Kastōr is a –tor-agent noun built on the Indo-European root *(s)ḱend– ‘to appear, become visible’, which, among others, underlies the Vedic root śad ‘to excel, triumph’ (García Ramón 1992). Significantly, Vedic śad, which mostly applies to the Dawn goddess Uṣas in the Rigveda, is once referred to the Divine Twins and their ‘swift (horses)’ (Pirart 1995: 160–161): In Rigveda 1.116, a hymn to the Aśvins enumerating their many achievements, the gods are said to have been exulting (śā́śadānā) thanks to their swift-speeding animals, compare

vīḷupátmabhir āśuhémabhir
devā́nāṃ vā jūtíbhiḥ śā́śadānā

Rigveda 1.116.2ab
As they were exulting in their firm-winged, swiftly impelled (steeds) or in the gods’ spur.
Although the term ‘horse’ (Vedic aśvá-) does not occur in the passage, it is possible to assume that āśuhémabhiḥ, instrumental plural to the compound āśuhéman– ‘swiftly impelling/impelled’ applies to these very animals, since both āśú– ‘swift’ and the root hi/hay ‘to impel’ commonly refer to the horses. To begin with, the u-stem adjective āśú-, matching Greek ōkús may reflect a reduplicated formation: *h1o-h1ƙ-ú-, which, in turn, may be etymologically related to the word ‘horse’, underlying, among others, Greek híppos, Vedic aśvá-, Avestan aspa-. All these terms may reflect *h1eƙu̯ó-, a thematic derivative to a u-stem *h1eƙ-u-, attested in Hittite and Hieroglyphic Luwian, compare Hittite ANŠE.KUR.RA-u– ‘horse’ and Hieroglyphic Luwian asu <EQUUSá-sù> (compare Kloekhorst 2008, s.v. ekku-). The semantic tie between ‘swiftness’ and ‘horse(s)’ is transparent and also well-reflected on the phraseological level. Horses are the swiftest animals on the earth, so both Greek and Indo-Iranian poetic texts preserve collocations and compounds of the type ‘swift horses’ or ‘possessing swift horses’, compare Greek collocations like ōkéas híppous, híppous … thoás, tákhe’ híppō, attested in hexameter poetry and elsewhere, the compound hippṓkēs (Bacchylides), and their Indo-Iranian phraseological counterparts Vedic āśuvàśva– ‘possessing swift horses’, áśvāḥ … āśávaḥ ‘horses … swift’, Avestan āsu.aspa– ‘possessing swift horses’, and aspā̊ŋhō […] āsauuō ‘swift … horses’ (on which see Schmitt 1967: 165–166). The Vedic verb hi/hay ‘to impel, spur’ and its compound (anu-hi, pra-hi and others), a congener of the second compound member (āśu-)héman– frequently applies to horses. Take, for instance, the compound aśvahayá– ‘impelling the horses’ or a passage like Rigveda 10.188.1ab prá nūnám … áśvaṃ hinota vājínam ‘Spur forth now … the prizewinning horse’.
In the light of these inner-Vedic phraseological evidence, it is thus safe to state that the combination āśuhémabhiḥ … śā́śadānā, which in RV 1.116.2 applies to the Divine Twins as a pair, is partly built with the same lexical material as the Greek formula Kástora … hippódamon: a derivative of Indo-European *(s)ḱend– ‘to appear, become visible’, i.e. Greek Kástōr and Vedic śā́śadānā, (perfect middle participle dual to Vedic śad), and derivatives to the ‘swiftness-root’ *h1eƙ-u-, Greek hippó(-damos) and Vedic āśu(-héman-). [1]
García Ramón, J.L. 1988–1990. “Homérico κέκασμαι : védico śāśad-, protoario *sćand-, IE *(s)ḱend– ‘aparecer, hacerse visible.’” Die Sprache 34.27–58.
———. 1992. “Mycénien ke-sa-do-ro /Kessandros/, ke-ti-ro /Kestilos/, ke-to /Kestōr/: grec alphabétique Aἰvησιμβρότα, Αἰvησίλαoς, Αἰvήτωρ et le nom de Cassandra.” In: J.P. Olivier (ed.): Mykenaïka: Actes du IXe Colloque international sur les textes mycéniens et égéens organisé par le Centre de l’antiquité grecque et romaine de la Fondation hellénique des recherches scientifiques et l’École française d’Athènes (Athènes, 2–6 octobre 1990), 239–255. Athènes: E.F.A.: K.E.R.A./Paris: Diffusion de Boccard.
Ginevra, R. 2022. “On Chariots and at Sea – Indo-European Gods of Mobility: Old Norse Njǫr.r, Vedic Sanskrit Nā́satya-, and Proto-Indo-European *nes-ḗt-/-.t- ‘returning (safely home), arriving (at the desired goal).” In S.W. Jamison, B. Vine, and D. Goldstein (eds.): Proceedings of the 32nd Annual UCLA Indo-European Conference. Hamburg: Buske.
Gotō, Toshifumi. 2009. “Aśvín and Nā́satya in the Rgveda and their prehistorical background.” In: Toshiki Osada, Noriko (eds.): Proceedings of the Pre-Symposium of RHIN and 7th ESCA Harvard-Kyoto Roundtable, 253–83. Kyoto: Research Institute for Humanity and Nature.
Jackson [Rova], P. 2006. The Transformations of Helen: Indo-European Myth and the Roots of the Trojan Cycle. Dettelbach.
Jamison, S.W., and J.P. Brereton. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kloekhorst, A. 2008. Etymological Dictionary of the Hittite Inherited Lexicon. Leiden/Boston: Brill.
Mannhardt, W. 1875. “Die lettischen Sonnenmythen.” Zeitschrift für Ethnologie 7.73–104, 209–44, 281–330.
Nagy, G. 1990. Greek Mythology and Poetics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
———. 2013. The Ancient Greek Hero in 24 Hours. Cambridge MA. Online: http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_NagyG.The_Ancient_Greek_Hero_in_24_Hours.2013.
———. 2016. “Helen of Sparta and her very own Eidolon.” Classical Inquiries. Online: https://classical-inquiries.chs.harvard.edu/helen-of-sparta-and-her-very-own-eidolon/.
Pirart, É. 1995. Les Nāsatyas. Liège: Droz.
Schmitt, R. 1967. Dichtung und Dichtersprache in indogermanischer Zeit. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz.
 
Laura Massetti 2022.10.26
κράτος (Krátos)
The substantive krátos (κράτος) has a variegated semantics. Its meaning ranges from ‘power’ to ‘physical strength’, compare Il. 7.142 ἔπεφνε δόλῳ, οὔ τι κράτεΐ γε ‘he slew him by guile, not by strength.’ For this reason, personified Krátos is brother of Bíē, according to Hesiod’s Theogony, compare

Στὺξ δ᾽ ἔτεκ᾽ Ὠκεανοῦ θυγάτηρ Πάλλαντι μιγεῖσα
Ζῆλον καὶ Νίκην καλλίσφυρον ἐν μεγάροισιν·
καὶ Κράτος ἠδὲ Βίην ἀριδείκετα γείνατο τέκνα

Hesiod Theogony 383–385
Stux, daughter of Okeanos, joined with Pallas and begot Zêlos and trim-ankled Níkē in the house. And (she) also generated Krátos and Bíē, wonderful children.
However, as Breuil (1989:25) points out, in traditional hexameter poetry, krátos has often ‘an abstract value, it expresses a relationship, and does not designate perceptible, countable objects’ (translation from French original: Massetti). For this reason, in a variety of contexts, it is possible to render the term as ‘overpower, victory.’ Take, for instance:

τείρεσθαι Τρῶας, μέγα δὲ κράτος εἶναι Ἀχαιῶν
Iliad 6.387
The Trojans were sorely pressed, and great victory rested with the Achaeans.
As for the etymology of the term, krátos reflects a neutral s-stem *kr̥-te/os- from an Indo-European root with the shape *kret-, whose meaning may be reconstructed as ‘to be superior.’ Further derivatives to the same root are preserved in Greek and can be recognized as ‘Caland-derivatives’, namely, among others: the thematic adjectives κραταιός and κρατερός ‘strong, mighty’; the comparative and superlative forms κρείττων/κρείσσων (kreíttōn/kreíssōn) ‘more/the most powerful/victorious’ and κράτιστος/κάρτιστος (krátistos/kártistos) ‘the best’; the first compound member κρατι-/καρτι- (krati-/karti-); the u-stem adjective κρατύς (kratús) ‘mighty’; the verb κρατύνομαι (kratúnomai) ‘to prepare krátos, that is, superiority’ (Nagy 1999, 5§25, n. 51, who stresses that krátos ‘superiority’ is opposed to ákhos ‘grief’).
In his 1969 book on Indo-European institutions, Benveniste proposed that krátos is an etymological congener of two Indo-Iranian u-stem substantives, which display a great formal resemblance to it: Vedic krátu- ‘resolve’ and Avestan xratu- ‘guiding intellect.’
Indeed, these terms share a variety of collocations with Greek krátos, such as, among others, the combination with

the Indo-European root *dheh1 ‘to put/set’, compare Iliad 1.509–510 ἐπὶ Τρώεσσι τίθει κράτος ‘give superior power/victory to the Trojans’, Rigveda 1.123.13b krátum asmā́su dhehi ‘place resolve in us’;
the Indo-European root *deh3 ‘to give’, compare Iliad 11.318–319 […] ἐπεὶ νεφεληγερέτα Ζεύς || Τρωσὶν δὴ βόλεται δοῦναι κράτος ἠέ περ ἡμῖν ‘for cloud-gatherer Zeus will give superiority [in battle]/victory to the Trojans rather than to us’, Rigveda 8.62.7a devā́ḥ ánu krátum daduḥ / bhúvo víśvasya gópatiḥ ‘all the gods conceded heroism and resolve (to you). You became the herdsman of all’;
the Indo-European root *bher- ‘to bring’, which lies at the basis of the man’s name Φερεκράτης (Attica) and the collocation φέρω … κράτος (compare Iliad 13.486) ‘to bear/bring victory’, matching Vedic (ā́-)bhar … krátu- ‘to bring resolve’ (Rigveda 7.32.26a) and Avestan auua.bar- … xratu- ‘bestow (i.e. bring) guiding thought’ (Yašt 17.2).
The phraseological matches support that an etymological tie exists between Greek krátos, Vedic krátu- and Avestan xratu-, since all these words can be understood as derivatives to a root *kret- and can be framed within the ‘Caland-system.’
Benveniste, É. 1969. Le vocabulaire des institutions indo-européennes. Paris: Minuit.
Breuil, J. L. 1989. “Κράτος et sa famille chez Homère: étude sémantique.” In Études homériques. Séminaire de recherche sous la direction de Michel Casevitz, ed. M. Casevitz, 17–53. Lyon: Maison de l’orient méditerranéen.
Massetti, L. In press. “A comparative lens on κρατὺς Ἀργεϊφόντης: meaning, etymology and phraseology.” Classical Quarterly.
Nagy, G. 1999. The Best of the Achaeans. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_NagyG.The_Best_of_the_Achaeans.1999.
Trümpy, H. 1950. Kriegerische Fachausdrücke im griechischen Epos. Freiburg: Paulusdruckerei.
 
Laura Massetti, 2021.10.29
Κύκνος and κύκνος (Kúknos and kúknos)
Kúknos (Κύκνος) is a son of Ares, who takes control over Apollo’s grove at Itonos. He challenges Herakles in a duel and gets killed, even though he receives help by his father, the War-god himself (on the homonymous Kúknos, son of Poseidon and enemy of Achilles in Pindar and in the Cypria see Nagy 1990, ch. 14). The personal name Kúknos is identical to the name of the ‘swan’, kúknos (κύκνος). Therefore, ancient scholars and commentators have sporadically tried to reconstruct a connection between Kúknos and the swan. For instance, according to Eustathius of Thessalonica, the episode of Kúknos ended with a katasterismós ‘transformation [of a character] into a star’: after being defeated by Herakles, Kúknos became the constellation of the Swan.
The personal name Kúknos has a transparent etymology. It is a no-derivative to an Indo-European root with a meaning ‘to blaze up’ reconstructed as *ƙeu̯k– by LIV2 (331) and as *(s)keu̯k– by Lubotsky (2001:25). Derivatives of the root are well attested in the Indo-Iranian languages, compare Vedic śócati ‘glows, burns’, Young Avestan saociṇt– ‘glowing, burning’. Nominal derivatives of the same root can be framed in the ‘Caland system’. This is “a certain subset of Indo-European roots that take a more or less well-defined subset of Indo-European nominal suffixes that stand in a close derivational relationship and can be thought of as mutually implying one another” (Rau 2009:70). Caland-derivatives usually behave in the same way as Greek kûdos (κῦδος, s-stem) ‘glory’, kudrós (κυδρός, ro-adjective) ‘glorious’, kudi° in kudiáneira (κυδι-άνειρα, i-first compound member) ‘bestowing glory upon the men’, kudnós (κυδνός, no-adjective) ‘famous’.
According to the same pattern, among the Indo-Iranian derivatives of Indo-European *ƙeu̯k– (or *[s]keu̯k-) we count:

 

– adjectives and first compound members in –ro– (*ƙuk-ró- or *(s)kuk-ró-), compare Vedic śukrá- ‘clear, white, light’, śukrávarṇa- ‘bright-colored’, Avestan suxra- ‘red, fire-colored’;
– adjectives and first compound members in –i– (*ƙuk-i– or *(s)kuk-i-), compare Vedic śúci– ‘clear, white, light’; śúcivarṇa– ‘bright-colored’;
– second compound members in –s– (*ƙeu̯k-es– or *(s)keu̯k-es-), compare Vedic sahásraśokas– ‘emitting a thousand flames’.
An adjectival derivative in –no-, shaped *ƙuk-nó-/*(s)kuk-nó– (with possible accent retraction), with a putative meaning ‘glowing’, could perfectly fit into the same system. Greek Kúknos could exist beside Vedic śukrá-, Avestan suxra– and Vedic śúci° in the same way as Greek kudnós (κυδνός) exists beside Greek kudrós (κυδρός) and kudi-áneira (κυδιάνειρα).
The etymology of Kúknos can be supported through the analysis of the Greek phraseology. In Hesiod’s Shield, the entry scene of Kúknos and Ares remarkably insists on the semantic field of ‘fire’ and ‘light’, compare:

 

εὗρε γὰρ ἐν τεμένει ἑκατηβόλου Ἀπόλλωνος
αὐτὸν καὶ πατέρα ὅν Ἄρην, ἄατον πολέμοιο,
τεύχεσι λαμπομένους σέλας ὣς πυρὸς αἰθομένοιο,
ἑσταότ᾽ ἐν δίφρῳ· χθόνα δ᾽ ἔκτυπον ὠκέες ἵπποι
νύσσοντες χηλῇσι, κόνις δέ σφ᾽ ἀμφιδεδήει

 

Hesiod Shield 58–62
He (: Herakles) found in the precinct of far-shooting Apollo him (: Kúknos) and his father Ares, never sated with war. Their armor shone like a flame of blazing fire as they two stood in their chariot: their swift horses struck the earth and pawed it with their hoofs, and the dust rose like smoke about them
πᾶν δ᾽ ἄλσος καὶ βωμὸς Ἀπόλλωνος Παγασαίου
λάμπεν ὑπὸ δεινοῖο θεοῦ τευχέων τε καὶ αὐτοῦ
πῦρ δ᾽ ὣς ὀφθαλμῶν ἀπελάμπετο.

 

Hesiod Shield 70–72
And the entire grove and the altar of Pagasaean Apollo flamed because of the dread god and because of his arms; as fire flashed as from the eyes
The comparison between Kúknos and ‘fire’ seems to be not limited to the scenes in which he fights side by side with his father. Hesiod compares dying Kúknos to a tree struck by a smoky thunderbolt:

 

ἤριπε δ᾽, ὡς ὅτε τις δρῦς ἤριπεν ἢ ὅτε πεύκη
ἠλίβατος, πληγεῖσα Διὸς ψολόεντι κεραυνῷ·

 

Hesiod Shield 421–423
And (Kyknos) fell as an oak falls or a lofty pine that is stricken by the smoky thunderbolt of Zeus
Significantly, in Old Indic, Vedic śukrá-, śúci– and their compounds apply to Agni, the fire-god, compare:

 

agníḥ śúcivratatamaḥ
śúcir vípraḥ śúciḥ kavíḥ
śúcī rocata ā́hutaḥ

 

Rigveda 8.44.21, Jamison – Brereton 2014
Agni, best possessor of flaming commandments, flaming inspired poet, flaming sage poet, flaming he shines when he is bepoured.
pāvakávarcāḥ śukrávarcā
ánūnavarcā úd iyarṣi bhānúnā

 

Rigveda 10.140.2ab, Jamison – Brereton 2014
(Agni) Of pure luster, of gleaming luster, of unfailing luster, you rise up with your radiance.
The ‘fiery’ nature of Kúknos may root in a poetic topos. In several Indo-European traditions, armed or fighting warriors are compared to fire and light (West 2007:455–458). In Iliad 5.4–7, Athena, who is standing by Diomedes, lights a flame from his helmet and shield, from his head and shoulders (compare Iliad 5.4 δαῖέ οἱ ἐκ κόρυθός τε καὶ ἀσπίδος ἀκάματον πῦρ “she lighted up an exhausted fire from the helmet and the shield”). In Iliad 18 (vv. 205–214, 225–7), Athena surrounds Achilles with a golden nimbus so that the hero emanates fire. In other Indo-European traditions, the epiphany of warriors is not less spectacular: the Old Indic hero Rāma, protagonist of the Sanskrit epic Rāmāyaṇa, burns like a smokeless flame before going to battle (Rāmāyaṇa 3.23.15+); in the Irish tradition the lúan laith ‘hero’s light’ glows upon the Cú Chulainn (Campanile 1990:20–24). It is thus possible that Kúknos is the ‘Glowing (warrior)’ par excellence, as he might ultimately embody the ‘warrior’s fire’.
As for the etymology of kúknos (κύκνος) ‘swan’, it is commonly accepted that kúknos is to be traced back to the same Indo-European as the personal name Kúknos. The semantics of name of the ‘swan’ may thus hint at the white color of the animal, which is referred to in a variety of contexts, compare, for instance, χιονόχρως κύκνου (Euripides Helen 215–216) “of a snow-white swan”; στίλβουσι δ’ ὥστε ποταμίου κύκνου πτερόν (Euripides Rhesus 618) “they dazzle like the wing of a river swan.” However, it is possible that kúknos ‘swan’ has to be kept apart from Kúknos ‘son of Ares’. On the basis of the Lithuanian verb šaukiù ‘to cry, call’ and Tocharian B verb śauśäṃ ‘to call’, Young Avestan saocaiia– ‘mockery’ LIV2 (331) and Cheung (2007:340) set up an Indo-European root *ƙeu̯k– ‘to cry (out)’, which, as such, is possibly homophone with *ƙeu̯k– ‘to glow.’ The same root is likely to underlie the Old Indic bird name śúka– ‘parrot’, and, I will propose, the first member of compound of Vedic śúcikranda-, a hapax eiremenon with a second compound member to the Vedic root krand ‘to roar’, compare:

 

śúcikrandaṃ yajatám pastíyā̀nām
bŕ̥haspátim anarvā́ṇaṃ huvema

 

Rigveda 7.97.5cd
We would invoke the loud roaring [śúcikranda-, ‘brightly roaring’ trans. Jamison – Brereton] one, worthy of the sacrifice of the dwelling places, unassailing Br̥haspati.
A thematic derivative śúka– [*ƙúk-o-] and a first compound member śúci° [*ƙúki°] together with an adjective (substantivized) form kúknos [*ƙúk-no-] can be framed in the Caland system. According to this etymology, the ‘swan’ could be identified as the ‘bird, which cries up’. A meaning of this description is highly compatible with the descriptions of swans preserved by the Greek and Latin literary sources. As pointed out by Nagy (1994§§28–29) classical texts refer to the swan as to the crying or singing animal, compare Hesiod Shield 315–316 κατ᾽ αὐτὸν || κύκνοι ἀερσιπόται μεγάλ᾽ ἤπυον “over it swans were soaring and calling loudly” (compare also (Homeric Hymn to Apollo 1, Euripides Phaethon 78, Hercules 692, Euripides Iphigenia in Tauris 1104, Aristophanes Birds 769–773+). Therefore, in a complementary fashion, the “swan is the archetypal poet” (Nagy 1994§29). In a renowned passage of the Phaedo Plato specifies that swans sing their most beautiful song out of joy, when they are about to die:

 

καί, ὡς ἔοικε, τῶν κύκνων δοκῶ φαυλότερος ὑμῖν εἶναι τὴν μαντικήν, οἳ ἐπειδὰν αἴσθωνται ὅτι δεῖ αὐτοὺς ἀποθανεῖν, ᾄδοντες καὶ ἐν τῷ πρόσθεν χρόνῳ, τότε δὴ πλεῖστα καὶ κάλλιστα ᾄδουσι, γεγηθότες ὅτι μέλλουσι παρὰ τὸν θεὸν ἀπιέναι οὗπέρ εἰσι θεράποντες.
Plato Phaedo 84e
And you seem to think I am inferior in prophetic power to the swans who sing at other times also, but when they feel that they are to die, sing most and best in their joy that they are to go to the god whose servants they are.
The connection between swans and singing was so close that, in another passage from the Republic (620a), Plato states that the soul of Orpheus chooses to reincarnate as a swan since “the choice was determined for the most part by the habits of their former lives.” Finally, in a later attested tradition the transformation of Kúknos, son of Sthenelos, into a swan is directly put in connection with the mourning song with which Kúknos sang for Phaethon, compare

 

Namque ferunt luctu Cycnum Phaethontis amati,
populeas inter frondes umbramque sororum
dum canit et maestum Musa solatur amorem,
canentem molli pluma duxisse senectam,
linquentem terras et sidera voce sequentem.

 

Vergil Aeneid 10.189
For legends tell that Cycnus, for his Phaethon so dear lamenting loud beneath the poplar shade of the changed sisters, made a mournful song to soothe his grief and passion: but erewhile, in his old age, there clothed him as he sang soft snow-white plumes, and spurning earth he soared on high, and sped in music through the stars.
In conclusion, while the name Kúknos, son of Ares and enemy of Herakles, can be traced back to an Indo-European root meaning ‘glowing, blazing’ (Indo-European *ƙeu̯k– or *(s)keu̯k-), the animal name kúknos ‘swan’ could be etymologically connected to a different root (Indo-European *ƙeu̯k-) meaning ‘to utter a sound’. Both proposed explanations find support in the analysis of the ancient literary sources.
Campanile, E. 1990. La ricostruzione della cultura indoeuropea. Pisa.
Cheung, J. 2007. Etymological Dictionary of the Iranian Verb. Leiden/Boston.
Jamison, S., and J. Brereton. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. 3 vols. Oxford.
LIV2 = Rix, H., et al. 20012. Lexikon der indogermanischen Verben. Die Wurzeln und ihre Primärstammbildungen. Wiesbaden.
Lubotsky, A. 2001. “Reflexes of Proto-Indo-European *sk in Indo-Iranian.” Incontri Linguistici 24:25–57.
Nagy, G. 1990. Pindar’s Homer. The Lyric Possession of an Epic Past. Online edition, http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Pindars_Homer.1990.
———. 1994. “Copies and Models in Horace Odes 4.1 and 4.2.” Short Writings III, ch. 4. Online edition, http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.essay:Nagy.Copies_and_Models_in_Horace_Odes_4.1_and_4.2.1994.
Rau, J. 2009. Indo-European Nominal Morphology: The Decads and the Caland System. Innsbruck.
West, M. L. 2007. Indo-European Poetry and Myth. Oxford.
 
Laura Massetti 2020.09.21
Κύπρις (Kúpris)
Kúpris (Κύπρις) is an appellative of Aphrodite, which first occurs in the fifth book of the Iliad (5.330, 422, 458, 760, 883). According to an internal Greek etymology, the epithet Kuprogen ḗs (Κυπρογενής) was attached to the goddess ‘because she was born on sea-girt Cyprus’ (Κυπρογενέα δ’, ὅτι γέντο περικλύστῳ ἐνὶ Κύπρῳ, Hesiod Theogony 200); however, it is possible to separate Kúpris from Kúpros (the island Cyprus) and to consider the association as secondary.
The first attestations of Kúpris connect the appellative to the sphere of desire (as in Κύπριδος, ἥ τε θεοῖσιν ἐπὶ γλυκὺν ἵμερον ὦρσε, ‘of Kúpris, who aroused sweet longing among the gods’, Homeric Hymn to Aphrodite 5.2). Moreover, in classical and late Greek sources, kúpris means ‘sex’ (as in οἴνου δὲ μηκέτ᾽ ὄντος οὐκ ἔστιν κύπρις, ‘without wine there is no sex’, Euripides Bacchae 773).
It has long been suggested that Kúpris has to be traced back to an Indo-European root *keu̯p- ‘to experience a strong feeling (of desire)’ (Enmann 1886), which underlies the Latin verb cupiō ‘to desire’ and the divine name Cupidō, among others. More precisely, Kúpris can be related to some ró-adjectival forms, attested in three Indo-European branches, namely Italic, Celtic, and Anatolian:

 

  • the Sabellic adjective cyprum, glossed as bonum ‘good’ by Varro, which lived on in the divine appellative cupra dea (i.e. bona dea ‘Good Goddess’), and in the Italian toponym Cupra Marittima;
  • the South Picenian adverb < kuprí > (AQ 2, Capestrano) ‘beautifully’ (as a last reference, see Martzloff 2011:196);
  • the Old Irish compound accobor (reflecting *ad-kŭpro-) ‘desire’, related to the verb ad·cobra ‘he wishes, desires’;
  • the Lycian verb kupri– ‘to want’ (Serangeli: forthcoming), whose denominative formation matches the structure of the Old Irish verb.

This set of forms speaks for the existence of a -adjective, *kupró- ‘desirable’, which was substantivized into *kupri– ‘desire’ through the morpheme –i-. Kúpris is therefore the personification of ‘Desire’.

To sum up: Kúpris can be interpreted as an originally individualizing i-stem derivative built on an adjective with the affix *-r ó . The form originally meant ‘the Desire (in person)’ and came to be employed as an epithet and an appellative of Aphrodite as the ‘goddess of (sexual) desire’.
Wachter, R. 2001. Non-Attic Greek Vase Inscriptions. Oxford.
Enmann, A. 1886. Kritische Versuche zur ältesten griechischen Geschichte. Vol. 1: Kypros und der Ursprung des Aphroditekultus. Saint Petersburg.
Martzloff, V. 2011. “Les marques casuelles dans les documents paléosabelliques et la morphologie du génitif pluriel sud-picénien”. In Grammatical Case in the Language of the Middle East and Europe: Acts of the International Colloquium Variations, concurrence et évolution des cas dans divers domaines linguistiques, Paris 2–4 April 2007 (eds. M. Fruyt, M. Mazoyer and D. Pardee) 189–215. Chicago.
Massetti, L. 2016. “Two Lovely Names: On Κύπρις and Ἶρις”. Münchener Studien zur Sprachwissenschaft 70/1: 41–60.
Serangeli, M. Forthcoming. Sprachkontakt im alten Anatolien: Das Lykische aus synchroner und diachroner Perspektive. Ph.D. dissertation. University of Cologne.
 
Laura Massetti 2018.06.11
μάργος (Márgos)
The term márgos (μάργος) is commonly translated as ‘gluttonous, wanton’ and first occurs in traditional hexametrical poetry. On the one side, it is related to the verbs margaínō (μαργαίνω) and margáō (μαργάω) ‘to rage (in battle)’. On the other, it occurs in connection with the semantic field of ‘eating’ and ‘drinking’. For instance, in Odyssey 18.2–3, Iros is said to be reknowned for his gastéri márgēi (‘gluttonous belly’), that is to say, for the capacity of eating and drinking without end (… μετὰ δ’ ἔπρεπε γαστέρι μάργῃ / ἀζηχὲς φαγέμεν καὶ πιέμεν).
As Gregory Nagy points out (1979 12§8–10), gluttony belongs together with phthónos in the diction of praise poetry . Consequently, in praise poetry, márgos came to apply to ‘those whose words are inimical to the institution of praise’ (Nagy 1979 12§8). According to Ibycus, a quarrelsome man possesses the ‘glutton mouth of Strife’:

Ἔριδός ποτε μάργον ἔχων στόμα
“… having the márgon mouth of Éris”

(Ibycus fr. 311 a P, trans. Nagy)
It’s not a coincidence that Margī́tēs, a ‘speaking name’ etymologically related to márgos, is the name of a blame poet in the homonymous mock epic whose initial verses display a variety of similarities to the opening of Odyssey 18 (Nagy O. 18.001–004). The name Margī́tēs is the same type of another ‘speaking name’, Thersī́tēs. This personal name, which might be translated as ‘Mr. Bold’, is built on Greek thársos / thérsos ‘boldness’. However, and despite its basically positive semantics, Thersī́tēs is a negative character in the Iliad, who embodies the verbal ‘boldness of envy’ (confer Bacchylides 13.199 thersiepḗs phthónos).
The derivational history of márgos deserves close consideration. According to an internal Greek pattern, a verb pair -aínō and -áō points to a feminine noun. Just as huphaínō ‘to weave’ and hupháō ‘to weave’ exisist besides huphḗ ‘web’, margaínō ‘to rage’ and margáō ‘to rage’ may have existed besides a feminine form * margā́, which is unattested in alphabetical Greek. Such a feminine form might have been the starting point for internally deriving márgos as a possessive adjective (‘provided with the X’) to the feminine noun in question.
Interestingly, Mycenean might attest a feminine form margā- (García Ramón 2010: 87), namely: ma-ka. In the Thebes tablet Fq 254, ma-ka occurs in connection with a delivery of barley:

TH Fq 254   1 de-qo-no ḤỌṚD T 1 V 2̣ Z 3 o-te, a-pi-e-qe ke-ro-ṭạ
    2 pa-ta, ma-ka ΗORD Ṭ 1̣ V 2 Z 2 a-ko-da-mo V 2
“For the banquet HORD 14 l., when one had mentioned all the honorable ones of the ke-ro-si-ja, for the margā- /for Margas HORD 13.6 l., for Arkhodamos 3.2”
 

The term has been interpreted as /māi gāi/ ‘for mother earth’ by Ruijgh (1996) and as a dative /magāi/ ‘for the kneading’ by Palaima (2000–2001). Both these interpretations are problematic: /māi gāi/ ‘for mother earth’ is linguistically defendable, but incompatible with the context of the Thebes tablet Fq 254; /magāi/ ‘for the kneading’ is linguistically difficult since it does not match its alleged alphabetical Greek correspondent máza (μάζα, from *magi̯a-).

It is more likely that Mycenean ma-ka conceals /Margāi/ ‘for Margas’, the dative of a personal name, or/margāi/, dative of a feminine form margā-. Since ma-ka parallels de-qo-no /deikwno-/, alphabetical Greek deípnon ‘banquet’ in the tablet, and it is allotted a large amount of barley, the possible meaning of the noun may be ‘repast’ or ‘large repast’.
Both Mycenean ma-ka and Greek márgos can be traced back to the Indo-European root *merg- ‘to divide, cut’, which underlies the Hittite verb mark- / mark-ḫḫif ‘to separate, butcher’ as well as several words for ‘border(land)’, such as, among others, Young Avestan marəza- ‘borderland’, Latin margo, marginis ‘boundary’, Old Norse mǫrk– ‘forest, (border)land’ and Old Irish mruig ‘borderland’. As for Greek márgos and Mycenean ma-ka, they could reflect a syllabification marg- of the zero-grade (instead of the expected outcome *brag-), which could be explained as secondary and analogical to that of the full-grade *morg– or *merg-. This kind of syllabification is just like the one seen in the Mycenean and Greek congeners of the Indo-European root *kerp– ‘to seize’, Mycenean ka-po /karpos/, Alphabetical Greek karpós (καρπός) ‘fruit’. Both the -o-full-grade morg– and the -e-full-grade merg– are attested in Greek glosses:

Hesychius μ 869 L μέργιζε· ἀθρόως ἔσθιε
                                ‘mérgize : eat at once!’
Hesychius μ 1648 L μόργιον· μέτρον γῆς
                                  ‘mórgion : measure of land’
Hesychius μ 1649 L μόργος· φραγμός […]
                                  ‘mórgos : fencing in’
The Greek congeners of Indo-European *merg– ‘to divide, cut’ can thus be grouped in three main semantic fields: (a) ‘voracity’ (márgos, possibly Mycenean ma-ka, mérgize), (b) ‘to rage’ (margaínō, margáō) and (c) ‘border(land)’ (mórgos, mórgion). Semantic evolutions/developments of this kind partially match those identified by Michael Weiss (1998: 35–47) for the Indo-European root *h1erh2– ‘to divide’, which lies at the basis of both Hittite arḫāš ‘border’ and Greek ἔρανος ‘meal’.
In conclusion, the Greek term márgos can be traced back to the Indo-European root *merg– ‘to divide, cut’, whose congeners are widely attested in several branches of the Indo-European family. Greek cognates of Indo-European *merg– display a rich polysemy, which parallels that of other Indo-European roots with a similar meaning as *merg-.
García Ramón, José Luis. 2010. “Espace religieux, théonymes, épiclèses: À propos des nouveaux textes thébains.” Isabelle Boehm, and Sylvie Müller-Celka (eds.): Espace civil, espace religieux en Egée durant la période Mycénienne : approches épigraphique, linguistique et archéologique : actes des journées d’archéologie et de philologie mycéniennes tenues à la Maison de l’Orient et de la Méditerranée – Jean Pouilloux, les 1er février 2006 et 1er mars 2007, 73–92. Lyon.
Massetti, Laura. 2016. “The Belly of an Indo-European: Some Greek and Iranian Congeners of Indo-European *merg- ‘to divide, cut’.” David M. Goldstein, Stephanie W. Jamison, and Brent Vine (eds.): Proceedings oft he 27th Annual UCLA Indo-European Conference, 115-129. Bremen.
Nagy, Gregory. 1979. The Best of the Achaeans. Concepts of the Hero in the Archaic Greek Poetry. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_NagyG.The_Best_of_the_Achaeans.1999.
——. 2017. A sampling comments on the Iliad and the Odyssey. Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.essay:Nagy.A_Sampling_of_Comments_on_the_Iliad_and_Odyssey.2017.
Palaima, Thomas. 2000–2001. Review of TFC I. Minos 35–6: 475–86
Rujigh, Cornelius J. 1996. “La ‘déesse mère’ dans les textes mycénien.” Ernesto de Miro, Louis Godard, and Anna Sacconi (eds.): Atti e memorie del secondo congress internazionale di micenologia I. Roma—Napoli, 14–20 ottobre 1991, 453–457. Rome.
Weiss, Michael. 1998. “Erotica: On the Prehistory of Greek Desire”. Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 98:31–61.
 
Laura Massetti 2020.01.31
Μαρσύας (Marsúās)
Marsúās (Μαρσύας) is the name of a Phyrgian satyr who picked up the musical wind instrument known as the aulos ‘double-reed, pipe’ that had been thrown away by Athena. The goddess had invented the instrument, but she could not stand the fact that her cheeks were puffed up while she played it (for example, [Apollodorus] Library 1.24). Marsúās is thus recorded as the inventor of the music of the aulos by a variety of classical sources. For instance, in Plato’s Symposium (215ac), Alcibiades mentions the festive custom of peeling the outer layer of Marsyas’s figurines, which concealed smaller figures of gods on their inside. According to Nagy 2017 (ad Odyssey 22.437–479), Marsyas’s figurines probably concealed a smaller Apollo. Thus, in the framework of the ritual re-enactment of Apollo’s punishment, festive merriment counterbalanced the grim death of the outrageous (Greek ὑβριστής) satyr.
The proper name Marsúās has long been interpreted as a loanword (Buck 1909) from Young Avestan maršuiiā̊, genitive singular of a name maršuuī-*, attested only in Yašna 11.1 (yō mąm xvāstąm nōit̰ baxṣ̌ahe […] / haoiiā̊ vā maršuiiā̊, ‘who does not allot me, when I am ritually prepared [… except] for his own maršuī’). The term is commonly taken to be a Daēuuic word—a word that applies to the daēuuas, ‘the demons’, and to impious worshippers—glossed as Sanskrit duṣṭodaram, ‘bad belly’. In turn, maršuuī-* may be traced back to an Indo-European root *merǵ– ‘to cut’, reflecting a feminine noun built on a u-stem adjective, which derives from an s-stem (Massetti 2016: 122–126).
Some Greek phraseological elements allow us to reconstruct a connection between Marsúās and the image of the ‘belly’. To begin with, the proper name Marsúās is probably related to Greek marsippos/marsuppos (μάρσιππος/μάρσυππος), ‘pouch’, whereby marsip(p)os (μάρσιπ[π]ος) reflects a compound meaning ‘weight of marsu-’ (marsu-*, īpos ‘weight’, see Frigione 2017). This term denotes a leather bag, hanging from and weighing down the waistline like a belly. It is likely that the mythical prototype of the marsipos was the myth of Marsúās’s flaying, encapsulated in the Greek phrase ‘Marsuās’s skin’, (Μαρσύεω ἁσκός, Herodotus Histories 7.26.14; ἀσκός … Μαρσύου, Plato Euthydemus 285d). According to classical sources, Apollo flayed the satyr alive after defeating him in a musical competition and let his skin hang on a tree. Significantly, Nonnus of Panopolis visualizes Marsyas’s skin as resembling a ‘belly’, using the verb kolpóō (κολπόω) ‘to create a kolpos (bosom, lap, womb, fold)’ to describe it (compare Nonnus of Panopolis Dionysiaca 1.42–43, ἐξ ὅτε Μαρσύαο θεημάχον αὐλὸν ἐλέγξας / δέρμα παρῃώρησε φυτῷ κολπούμενον αὔραις ‘since he (Apollo) humiliated the god-fighting flute of Marsyas / and hung his skin, bellying in the breezes, on a tree’).
To sum up: It is likely that Mars úā s, as a mythological character, was shaped on an Iranian loanword, maršuuī-*, meaning ‘belly’, as supported by the Greek phraseological evidence. The ‘skin of Mars úā s’ was the first marsup(i)os, ‘pouch (that hangs on the belly)’, since Apollo hung the satyr’s skin on a tree with his belly to the wind.
Buck, C. D. 1909. “Greek Notes.” Indogermanische Forschungen 25:257–264.
Frigione, Ch. 2017. “Ipotesi su gr. Μαρσύας e gr. μάρσι/ύ(π)πος.” In Ancient Greek Linguistics: New Perspectives, Insights, and Approaches, ed. F. Logozzo and P. Poccetti, 811–824. Berlin.
Massetti, L. 2016. “The belly of an Indo-European: Some Greek and Iranian Cognates of IE *merǵ– ‘to Divide, Cut’.” In Proceedings of the 27th Annual UCLA Indo-European Conference, ed. D. M. Goldstein, S. W. Jamison, and B. Vine, 115–129. Bremen.
Nagy, G. 2017. “A sampling of comments on the Iliad and Odyssey.” http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hlnc.essay:Nagy.A_Sampling_of_Comments_on_the_Iliad_and_Odyssey.2017.
 
Laura Massetti 2018.05.29
Νέστωρ (Nestōr)
Νέστωρ, the name of the king of Pylos in Homer, is in form an agent noun ending in the IE agent suffix –tor. It is one of eighteen names in Homer with this suffix, some of which also occur as common nouns and all but one of which contain the root of a Greek verb. It is thus in a class of names that is unusually clear in meaning, even in the absence of a corresponding common noun. [1] Such is the case, for example, of Ἕκτωρ, whose role as ‘protector’ of Troy is closely linked with his name when he is said to ‘keep’ (ἔχειν) his city’s people. [2] Like Ἕκτωρ, Νέστωρ has no corresponding common noun, but unlike Ἕκτωρ Nestor’s name does not conjure anything up in the minds of readers of the Homeric poems beyond the vigorous and sagacious old man himself. [3]
This is not to say, however, that his name had no meaning within the Homeric poems themselves. In fact the name had a clear meaning which was subsequently lost, and which has now been recovered in light of the evidence of Linear B. The first element of Néstōr is the verbal root *nes– of the verb néomai ‘to return.’ This is plain enough, but Néstōr ‘the returner’ hardly seems a ‘significant name’, since any hero who, like Nestor, returned from Troy could have been so called. What was previously unsuspected is that in Néstōr the root *nes– has an active, transitive meaning, ‘bring back.’ In Linear B the personal name ne-e-ra-wo occurs on a Pylos tablet [4] and is interpreted as Nehe-lawos, from earlier *Nese-lawos ‘he who brings the war-folk back’. This name is of the same type as, for example, Age-lawos (Ἀγέλαος) ‘he who leads the war-folk’, which also occurs in Linear B, as a-ge-ra-wo. [5] In these names the first element (Nese-, Age-) is a transitive verb governing the object lawos. The transitive verb *néō ‘bring back’ is not otherwise attested, although this statement requires an important qualification to be discussed below. Mycenaean Nehe-lawos is the basis of Nestor’s father’s name, Nēleús, and thus of Nestor’s own patronymic, Nēlēiádēs ‘descendant of Neleus.’ [6] Nēleús is an Aeolic version of Nestor’s father’s name befitting his origin in Aeolian Thessaly. [7] The Ionic form of Nehe-lawos is Νείλεως (Neíleōs), a regular phonological outcome from the Mycenaean name. In Ionia the royal family of Miletus traced its origin to Nestor’s father, and they were thus called the Neleids. But they were also, in their local context, the Neileids, in claiming descent from Neíleōs, the legendary founder of Miletus from Athens. This figure was an Athenian descendant of the founder of Pylos; he was the basis of the claim by the Milesian royal family to have a proximate Athenian origin as well as a more distant Pylian origin. [8]
The Linear B evidence led quickly to the realization that Nestor the son had a name that repeated in part the name of Neleus the father, when the latter is understood as original *Nese-lawos: the father was ‘he who brings the war-folk back’ and the son was simply ‘he who brings back’. The first thought was that these were the names of an actual pair of rulers of Bronze Age Pylos, the founder of that city and his long-lived son. But the source of our information about both figures must be taken into account. The significant thing about the name Neleus is that the royal family of Miletus effectively had it as their name. The significant thing about the name Nestor is that everything we know about its bearer comes from his role in the two Homeric poems. Whereas Neleus was regarded as the Milesian family’s ancestor, his son Nestor was not. The line of descent was traced through another son of Neleus, Periklymenos. [9] Nestor was not the Neleids’ ancestor, but their epic hero. The root *nes– in his name undoubtedly relates to their name, but not in terms of ancestry. Nestor bears out his name on a wholly different plane.
For Nestor to have borne out his name in Homeric epic his name must still have been understood in Homeric epic, but was this the case? The evidence of Mycenaean Greek hardly counts when it comes to the understanding of 8/7th-century BC poets and audience. [10] But in fact there is strong evidence for a transitive verb *néō ‘bring back’ disguised as something else in the Odyssey. In Odyssey 18 Penelope recalls before the suitors what Odysseus told her to do if he failed to return from Troy by the time Telemachus came of age, namely to remarry. Odysseus began by telling her that he did not think all the Achaeans would ‘return home’ (ἀπονέεσθαι, 18.260) in view of the great prowess of the Trojan foe (18.261–264), and then he says: “therefore I do not know whether the god will save me or I shall die in Troy,” (τῶ οὐκ οἶδ’, ἤ κέν μ’ ἀνέσει θεός, ἦ κεν ἁλώω / αὐτοῦ ἐνὶ Τροίῃ, 18.265f.). Will save me must be what is meant by the phrase μ’ ἀνέσει, but the form ἀνέσει cannot give that meaning. [11] With the change of one vowel from μ’ ἀνέσει to με νέσει everything comes clear: νέσει here is the future of the hypothesized verb *néō and means ‘will bring back’, which gives perfect sense: “therefore I do not know whether the god will bring me back or I shall die in Troy.” The root *nes– in the middle verb ἀπονέεσθαι at the beginning of Odysseus’ speech is repeated five lines later in the active verb νέσει.
If the Homeric audience understood the verb νέσει in Odyssey 18.265 to mean ‘will bring back’ they would also have understood the name Νέστωρ as ‘he who brings back’. The meaning of Nestor’s name is in fact crucial to understanding his role in Odyssey 3, when he tells Telemachus about the ‘returns’ (νόστοι) of the Achaeans from Troy, including his own return. Telemachus wants to know the fate of his father and Nestor does tell him something about that, but in less than explicit terms. A close reading of his speech shows that he and Odysseus, who never disagreed with each other in counsel during the war, quarreled upon leaving Troy at the island of Tenedos on the very issue of ‘return’. Odysseus turned back to Troy where Agamemnon still remained, but Nestor fled in the opposite direction for home. When Nestor is understood to be ‘he who brings back’, Odysseus’ decision to part ways with him has a clear implication. This implication is made explicit when Nestor does for Diomedes what he did not do for Odysseus. Diomedes flees with Nestor and stays with him through each fraught turn across the Aegean until he is home in Argos three days later. Nestor, who sails on to Pylos, has done for Diomedes what his name says, he has brought him home. On the other hand Odysseus, whom Nestor has not brought home, has a νόστος of ten years awaiting him when he again leaves Troy. [12]
In the Iliad we get to the basis of Nestor’s function as ‘he who brings back’. In Iliad 11 Nestor motivates Patroclus to take Achilles’ place in battle by telling him how he once saved his own beleaguered people. Nestor alone among Neleus’ sons had been left to defend Pylos against neighbors who took advantage of the city’s weakened state. Pylos had earlier been sacked by Heracles, who slew Neleus’ other sons, in particular the redoubtable Periklymenos. As in Odyssey 3 to Telemachus, Nestor is less than explicit in Iliad 11 to Patroclus, but his message reduces to this, that as Nestor once took the place of his warrior brother Periklymenos to defend the Pylians in battle, Patroclus should now take the place of the absent warrior Achilles to defend the Achaeans in battle.
Nestor’s standing epithet in Homer is ἱππότα, the ‘horseman’. His story in Iliad 11 tells how he first became a warrior horseman by taking the place of his dead brother in battle. The youthful Nestor is shown earning his epithet ἱππότα when he slays the leader of the enemy horsemen and wins for himself horses and chariot with which to rout the foe, as he proceeds to do virtually single-handedly. As Odyssey 3 shows Nestor as Νέστωρ, ‘he who brings home’, Iliad 11 shows him in the other half of his dual nature. The phrase ἱππότα Νέστωρ, ‘the horseman Nestor’, in fact has deep roots in Indo-European, where twin gods, ancestral to the Dioskouroi, are differentiated from each other by terms related to ἱππότα on the one hand and Νέστωρ on the other hand. The evidence is in the Rig Veda, where the twin gods cognate with the Greek Dioskouroi are the Aśvins (Aśvinau/ Aśvinā). This name, cognate with Nestor’s epithet ἱππότα, means ‘possessors of horses’. [13] It is in the dual, designating both twins, but the Vedic twins also have a second name in the dual, Nāsatyā, which contains the root *nes– in a transitive sense, and is thus a close comparison for Greek Νέστωρ. The Vedic twins are ‘saviors’ of distressed mortals (a function they share with the Greek Dioskouroi), and their name has long been compared with the Germanic evidence for the root *nes-, in particular the causative verb found in Gothic (nasjan ‘to save’) and in the other branches of Germanic as well. [14] The name Nāsatyā is demonstrably old, [15] and while the verbal root in the name is clear, the form of the name is not obvious. The derivation I prefer begins with the Sanskrit cognate of Greek néomai, namely nasate, meaning ‘approach, resort to, join’ in attested Sanskrit. I propose that in Common Indo-Iranian an active verb *nasati ‘bring back’ was formed from the middle verb nasate ‘return’, just as in Greek the active verb *néō was formed from the middle verb néomai. [16] A syntagma composed of the third person singular verb *nasati and the relative pronoun ya-, *nasati-ya, was then nominalized with regular lengthening of the root vowel to produce Nāsatya-, literally ‘he who brings back’. [17]
In the Rig Veda the twin gods are for the most part viewed as an identical pair, and their two dual names thus each designate both twins. But the diction of the Rig Veda contrasts the two names in a way that correlates with distinctions between the twins found in Sanskrit epic in two of the heroes of the Mahabharata. The five heroes of the poem are all sons of different gods, and the two youngest are sons of the twin gods. One son, Nakula, is characterized as a warrior and is associated with horses, the other son, Sahadeva, is characterized as intelligent, and is associated with cattle. In a series of texts in the Rig Veda the two names of the twin gods are differentially associated with cattle and horses, the name Aśvinā ‘horsemen’ being associated with horses, and the name Nāsatyā ‘saviors’ being associated with cattle. [18] The two Vedic names can thus be paired with their two epic sons, such that Aśvinā properly designates the father of Nakula and Nāsatyā properly designates the father of Sahadeva. [19]
The combined evidence of the Mahabharata and the Rig Veda imply that one of the Vedic twins was a Nāsatya- ‘savior’ while the other was an Aśvin ‘horseman’, but the basis of this distinction is not explained in Indo-Iranian. For that we turn to the Greek Dioskouroi, where IE distinctions between the twins are more clearly preserved. One such distinction, which is also found in Vedic, is between the separate fathers of the two divine twins, the sky god on the one hand (Greek Zeus, Vedic Dyaus) and a mortal on the other hand (Greek Tyndareus, Vedic Sumakha). [20] In Greek the distinction between fathers is the basis of a distinction between the twins themselves, the immortal son of the sky god, Polydeuces, and his mortal brother, Castor. [21] The mortal Castor is further characterized as a warrior horseman who dies in battle, and who is then brought back to life by his immortal twin. [22] The singular Nāsatya- of Common Indo-Iranian should be interpreted in the light of the basic myth of the Greek twins, and given the meaning ‘he who brings back to life’. [23]
The verbal contrast in the two names of the Vedic twins, Nāsatyā and Aśvinā, can be posited for Indo-European when Greek ἱππότα Νέστωρ is compared. While the processes of noun formation are different in Indic and Greek, the contrast in both cases has a common core in the transitive root *nes– on the one hand and the noun *ekwos on the other hand, indicating an Indo-European origin for the contrast itself.
In Indo-European myth the mortal twin standing behind Indic Aśvinā and Greek ἱππότα was brought back to life by the immortal twin standing behind Indic Nāsatyā and Greek Νέστωρ. Nestor’s myth, however, is a variant of the Indo-European twin myth: when his mortal twin dies, he does not bring him back to life, but takes his place as a warrior horseman. He thus combines both twins of the Indo-European myth in one figure when he becomes ἱππότα Νέστωρ. This is the example he sets for Patroclus, who takes the place of Achilles in battle. Patroclus follows his example, but unlike Nestor he does not survive the experience. At his funeral the difference in outcome between Nestor’s youthful triumph and Patroclus’ tragic death is featured in the chariot race over which Nestor, along with Achilles, presides. The narrative is elliptic, as usual with Nestor, but close reading again reveals what is not spoken. The youthful Nestor, before he became a ‘horseman’ on the battlefield, lost a chariot race to a pair of twins, as he narrates himself, and he did so in spectacular fashion by crashing at the turning post. This he omits to say, but it can be worked out from the description of the twins to whom he lost, who each had a different function in the race. Nestor, on the other hand, knew only how to ‘incite’ with the whip, the function of one of the twins, not how to ‘restrain’ with the reins, the function of the other twin. [24] This fits his version of the twin myth, for he had only the function of the immortal twin, namely to ‘bring back to life’, but not yet the mortal twin’s function to ‘restrain’. Nestor’s failed chariot race has a retrospective relevance to Patroclus’ fate, as Nestor’s youthful triumph in combat had a prospective relevance to Patroclus’ day of glory when Nestor induced him to take Achilles’ place in battle. [25]
The etymology of Νέστωρ, with its roots in the Indo-European twin myth, relates to the etymology of Greek νόος ‘mind’ already preliminarily discussed in a separate entry. Reconstructed as *nosos, a verbal noun from the root *nes-, νόος has somehow to do with a ‘return to life’, and ‘consciousness’ has already suggested itself as what the noun originally designated. The question now is whether νόος was originally a ‘returning to life’ or a ‘bringing back to life’, either of which meanings seems possible to designate ‘consciousness’. There is in fact good reason to believe that νόος originated in the context of the twin myth and that the action of the immortal twin in bringing the mortal twin back to life is what defined νόος. The Dioskouroi still retain this basic element of the Indo-European twin myth, and Pindar’s description of what the immortal Polydeuces does for the mortal Castor clearly suggests ‘consciousness’. Given the choice between sharing his immortality with Castor or becoming entirely a god himself Polydeuces “chose the life of Castor who had perished in battle,” εἵλετ’ αἰῶνα φθιμένου Πολυδεύκης Κάστορος ἐν πολέμῳ: going to his brother’s side, Polydeuces “opened the eye, and then the voice of bronze-clad Castor,” ἀνὰ δ’ ἔλυσεν μὲν ὀφθαλμόν, ἔπειτα δὲ φωνὰν χαλκομίτρα Κάστορος (Pindar Nemean 10.59 and 90). [26]
The Dioskouroi come as close as it is possible to come to showing what νόος looks like as a ‘bringing back to life’. The Dioskouroi do not themselves embody the root *nes– or the word νόος, although they come close to doing that as well. [27] Their Vedic counterparts contain the root of νόος in their name Nāsatyā ‘they who bring back to life’, and their miraculous rescues and cures of mortals bear their name out, but the Vedic pair does not make explicit the foundational myth of the Indo-European pair in which one twin brings the other back to life. This myth is implied, as previously discussed, by Rig Vedic verses opposing the names Nāsatyā and Aśvinā and pairing the names differentially with ‘cattle’ and ‘horses’. The originally singular Nāsatya- ‘he who brings back to life’, who is implied by these paired oppositions, was marked by intelligence in opposition to the warlike nature of his brother. This is revealed in the ‘intelligence’ of the epic hero Sahadeva, the son of the divine twin once called the son of Dyaus in the Rig Veda, who is thus the counterpart of Polydeuces, the son of Zeus. The intelligence of this divine twin is implied by the epithet dasrā ‘miracle-working’, which is used in the dual of both twins in connection with their miraculous rescues and cures. Etymologically the epithet means ‘intelligent’, and it characterizes one twin in opposition to the other in Rig Vedic verses where cattle and horses are again contrasted, but instead of the name Nāsatyā standing in opposition to the name Aśvinā, the epithet dasrā stands in opposition to the name Aśvinā. [28] The name Nāsatyā and the epithet dasrā are to this extent interchangeable, and it is an easy step to take to say that the name Nāsatya– itself implies ‘intelligence.’ Vedic Nāsatya– ‘he who brings back to life’ is thus a valid comparison for Greek νόος, reconstructed as a ‘bringing back to life’.
The name Νέστωρ, reconstructed as ‘he who brings back to life’, is virtually equivalent to νόος, a ‘bringing back to life’, the difference being the difference between an agent noun and an action noun. Nestor’s variant of the twin myth precludes that he do for his brother what Polydeuces does for Castor, namely bring him back to life. Nestor thus does not enact the myth that defines νόος in its Indo-European context, but in his own variant of the myth his connection with νόος is nonetheless peculiarly marked. Beyond Homeric occurrences of the word that seem to make Nestor the very personification of νόος, [29] two episodes are especially noteworthy. In the chariot race for Patroclus, as discussed, Nestor himself characterizes the difference between the two twins who defeated him in his youthful race as the incitement of the whip on the one hand and the restraint of the reins on the other hand. In the chariot race itself Nestor’s son Antilochus reenacts what it meant for Nestor to use only the whip and to lose control of the reins. Antilochus does not crash at the turning post as his father did, but his rash maneuver to overtake Menelaos in a dangerously narrow pass is the reenactment of his father’s unrestrained incitement as a youth. [30] After the race Antilochus is forced to apologize to Menelaos, and his apology reveals that the incitement that characterizes him as a young man—and that once characterized his father as a youth, be it understood—is precisely a matter of νόος. “You know the transgressions of youth,” Antilochus says to his older opponent, “his νόος is swifter, but his μῆτις is slight,” (κραιπνότερος μὲν γάρ τε νόος, λεπτὴ δέ τε μῆτις, 23.590). In terms of the chariot race νόος is equated with the incitement of the whip. [31] Νέστωρ, before he became ἱππότα Νέστωρ, was, so to speak, all whip, which is to say that he was the embodiment of νόος.
The chariot race in Iliad 23, when closely read, reveals that the virtual equivalence between the agent noun Νέστωρ and the action noun νόος was very much alive in the minds of poets and audience in the Homeric era. Nestor, as already discussed, was the epic hero of the Neleid family of kings in Miletus. Traditions about the youthful Nestor must have been their special, even unique inheritance. These traditions preserved the myth of ἱππότα Νέστωρ, who takes the place of his fallen brother on the battlefield. The old man Nestor, on the other hand, would have been created in the context of Homeric epic itself. As seen, the aged Nestor in the foreground of the Iliad and the Odyssey acts out his name, ‘he who brings home’, in Odyssey 3. [32] Since Νέστωρ is virtually equated with νόος in the story of his youthful chariot race forming the background to the chariot race in Iliad 23, there is good reason to think that the same connection is present when he acts out his name as the aged hero in Odyssey 3. [33] To follow Nestor as he brings Diomedes home to Argos is to watch νόος in operation. The key to Nestor’s action is that he correctly chooses to go in one direction and not another until the voyage is successfully completed, and his decision in each case depends upon his correctly interpreting a sign. The decisions begin in Troy when the Atreidai themselves split from one another and Nestor does not remain in Troy with Agamemnon but sails with Menelaos to Tenedos. On Tenedos he quarrels with Odysseus and flees for home, as Odysseus turns back to Troy and Agamemnon. He does so because he ‘recognizes’ that ‘the god planned evil’ (φεῦγον, ἐπεὶ γίνωσκον, ὃ δὴ κακὰ μήδετο δαίμων, 3.166); Diomedes, who flees with him (φεῦγε δὲ Τυδέος υἱὸς Ἀρήϊος, 3.167), has the benefit of his insight into how things stand with the gods. Οn the island of Lesbos all hesitate and ask for a sign whether to cut straight across the Aegean to Euboea or to take a safer route by way of the islands, and the god gives them a sign (ᾐτέομεν δὲ θεὸν φῆναι τέρας· αὐτὰρ ὅ γ’ ἥμιν/ δεῖξε, καὶ ἠνώγει πέλαγος μέσον εἰς Εὔβοιαν/ τέμνειν, ὄφρα τάχιστα ὑπὲκ κακότητα φύγοιμεν, “We were asking the god to show a sign; he then gave us one and bade us cut across the middle of the sea to Euboea, that we might escape the evil as quickly as possible,” 3.173–175). Nestor does not say who it was that correctly read this sign, [34] but signs are Nestor’s peculiar domain, in the Iliad as well as the Odyssey. [35] Nestor does not need to take credit for choosing the right course; it can only have been he who correctly read the sign at this most critical turning point on the return home.
Binary decisions fit well with Νέστωρ ‘he who brings back to life’ as a twin figure. But clearly his action, if it is understood as the operation of νόος, a ‘bringing back to life’, reflects a more evolved mental process than simply ‘consciousness’. The noun νόος ‘mind’ was of course not restricted in use to its original meaning, any more than any noun is bound in meaning to its etymology, and νόος has a normal range of meanings in Homeric and later Greek. It required a special medium, that of traditional poetry, and a special channel, the traditions of a particular family, for etymology to remain alive in this case. It is telling that it is in the chariot race of the youthful Nestor that νόος appears closest to its origin in the Indo-European twin myth, and that it is in the νόστος of the aged Nestor that νόος, as personified by this aged figure, has become something more evolved. [36]
I save until the end of this entry on Νέστωρ a point left unaddressed at the start of the entry on νόος. There the Mycenaean name Wiphinoos is cited in support of the derivation of nóos from the root *nes-, on the tacit assumption that the name is valid evidence for the noun. While it is clear that the Linear B name contains the root *nes– in its second element –noos, more needs to be said about the relationship of the name to the noun nóos ‘mind.’ Wiphinoos in fact means ‘he who brings back by his strength’, where –noos contains the root *nes-, and the formation of the name is like that of the Homeric epithet laossóos ‘inciting the warfolk’, in which –soos contains the root of seúō ‘incite’ (IE *ki̯eu̯-). This raises the question whether the name Wiphinoos may have nothing to do with the noun nóos, and there may instead be two different kinds of compounds ending in –noos, that represented by Mycenaean Wiphinoos, in which –noos means ‘bringing back’, and that in which – noos means ‘mind.’ [37] There are in fact two such kinds of compounds, but it is implausible to think that they are unrelated. The Mycenaean name instead confirms the active sense of the root *nes– in both the name Néstōr and the noun nóos. Another name formed exactly like Wiphinoos sheds light on the question. Alkínoos, the name of the Phaeacian king in the Odyssey, has virtually the same meaning as Wiphinoos, ‘he who brings home by his might/strength’. The name clearly fits the function of the Phaeacian king in the Odyssey, and it also relates directly to the name Néstōr. The Phaeacian king, who brings Odysseus home, is in fact modeled on Nestor, [38] whose role in the Odyssey is pointedly not to bring Odysseus home. Alkínoos is a second Nestor and his name is meant to evoke Nestor’s name and their common function of ‘bringing home’. By its form the name also evokes the noun nóos as a ‘bringing back to life and light’. The name is a clear indication of the root connection between nóos ‘mind’ and Néstōr, the memory of which Homeric epic has retained.
 
[ back ] 1. For the eighteen names in –tor see HN 23 [§1.13]. (HN = Frame, Douglas. 2009. Hippota Nestor. Hellenic Studies Series 37. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Frame.Hippota_Nestor.2009.)
Four of the eighteen names in –tor also occur as common nouns in Homer, three occur as common nouns in later Greek, and two correspond to agent nouns in –ter in later Greek.
[ back ] 2. Iliad 24.730 (Andromache’s lament): ἔχες δ’ ἀλόχους κεδνὰς καὶ νήπια τέκνα. ‘Hector Protector’ is a familiar phrase in English from a children’s rhyme. A common noun ἕκτωρ does occur in later Greek, but not in the sense of a personal ‘protector’. It is rather a term found in Hesychius for ‘hairnet’ or, in the plural, ‘pegs on a chariot pole’.
[ back ] 3. Nestor is the archetypal representative of old age in such texts as Propertius 2.13.46–50 and Juvenal 10.246–255, where he is characterized as having lived too long.
[ back ] 4. PY Fn 79.5.
[ back ] 5. The Linear B form could also represent Arkhe-lawos, from ἄρχειν, ‘rule.’
[ back ] 6. The Linear B name, as it occurs on the Pylos tablet, refers to a recipient of grain and olives, hence a humble figure and not the city’s king.
[ back ] 7. The first syllable of Nēleús represents an Aeolic contraction (-ee- > -ē-), the second syllable replaces earlier –lawos with the ‘short form’ –leus; for such short-form names see HN 31 [§1.19] n. 51.
[ back ] 8. Hellanicus FGrHist 323a F 23 for the genealogy; Herodotus 9.97 for Neíleōs as the proper form of the name of the founder of Miletus. Cf. HN 29–30 [§1.17–§1.18].
[ back ] 9. Hellanicus FGrHist 323a F 23. Cf. HN 17 [§1.8].
[ back ] 10. Presumably the descendants of the Athenian Neíleōs in Miletus still understood their name through family tradition but the question is how much wider that knowledge extended.
[ back ] 11. Formally ἀνέσει could be a future from the same verb as found in Homeric aorists from the root *sed-, such as the participle ἀνέσαντες ‘having placed upon’ (Iliad 13.657), but the meaning of this verb is clearly wrong in Odyssey 18. The verb ἀνίημι in the meaning ‘release’ vaguely fits the context, but the future of this verb is not ἀνέσει but ἀνήσει with a long vowel.
[ back ] 12. Nestor’s role in Odyssey 3 is discussed in HN 173–193 [§2.56– §2.70].
[ back ] 13. Greek ἵππος and Sanskrit aśva– go back to IE *ekwos ‘horse’.
[ back ] 14. For the Germanic evidence cf. the CIGE entry for Greek νόος.
[ back ] 15. It occurs in Mitanni, where the same twin gods are designated as in Vedic, and in an Iranian singular form; for the latter cf. n.19 below. Cf. HN 59 [§1.42].
[ back ] 16. The active verb postulated for Indo-Iranian and reconstructed in Greek could go back to Indo-European, or both could have been created independently in separate Indo-European branches.
[ back ] 17. The Rig Veda often requires Nāsatyā to be scanned as Nāsatiyā, or alternatively as Naasatyā, but the latter rhythm is linked to a secondary folk etymology of the twins’ name as the ‘not untrue ones’ (na-asatya-). The rhythm Nāsatiyā on the other hand would reflect the proposed etymology (nasati-ya). This derivation of the name Nāsatyā is based on a similar derivation proposed by Gregory Nagy for Iranian xšāyaθiya‑ ‘king’ as ‘he who has power’; cf. HN 89–90 [§1.67].
[ back ] 18. The basic text is Rig Veda 2.41.7: gómad ū ṣú nāsatyā / áśvāvad yātam aśvinā / vartī́ rudrā nṛpāyyam, “Quickly come (ū ṣúyātam) along the path (vartī́) rich in cattle, you Nāsatyā; quickly come along the path rich in horses, you Aśvinā; quickly come, you rudrā, along the man-protecting (nṛpāyyam) path.” This is a gayatri verse consisting of three eight-syllable segments, the first two of which are parallel in structure to articulate the oppositions in question, while the third segment stands apart in its structure.
[ back ] 19. The Vedic names are ‘elliptic duals’ and mean, respectively, ‘the Aśvin and his brother’, and ‘the Nāsatya- and his brother’. A singular Nāsatya- occurs in one verse of the Rig Veda 4.3.6, and Nåŋhaiθya, the Iranian cognate of Nāsatyā, also belongs to a singular figure; cf. HN 89 [§1.67] n. 207.
[ back ] 20. Vedic Sumakha, who is otherwise unknown, can be assumed to be mortal by the very fact that he is not known otherwise. Note that both Greek twins are called Dioskouroi ‘sons of Zeus’ and Tyndaridai ‘sons of Tyndareus’, although each name belongs properly to only one of the twins; cf. the previous note on the ‘elliptic duals’ in Vedic.
[ back ] 21. This distinction is also to be assumed for the Vedic twins, although the Rig Veda has no interest in it. As gods the twins act as an undifferentiated pair.
[ back ] 22. Pindar Nemean 10 recounts the myth; the relevant verses 59 and 90 are quoted below in the text. Cf. HN 75–76 [§1.58].
[ back ] 23. The Greek myth is the basic one for the Dioskouroi in that it defines the moment when they are transformed from heroes into gods. The pair in fact hovers between the two statuses in cult. It is in their nature as twins to be close to mortals on the one hand and close to gods on the other hand; cf. HN 77–80 [§1.60].
[ back ] 24. Iliad 23.641–642: οἳ δ’ ἄρ’ ἔσαν δίδυμοι· ὃ μὲν ἔμπεδον ἡνιόχευεν,/ ἔμπεδον ἡνιόχευ’, ὃ δ’ ἄρα μάστιγι κέλευεν. Cf. HN 133–134 [§2.20].
[ back ] 25. The same twins who defeated Nestor in the chariot race appear in the battle where he triumphs. The twins’ father Poseidon rescues them from his path now that he, as a newly minted horseman, is a match for a pair of twins. Cf. HN 107–113 [§2.4– §2.6]. Nestor’s role in Iliad 11 is analyzed in HN 105–130 [§2.1– §2.18], his role in Iliad 23 in 131–172 [§2.19– §2.55].
[ back ] 26. Cf. HN 93–94 [§1.69]. An alternation between ‘consciousness’ and ‘unconsciousness’ is clearly suggested by the Dioskouroi when they are represented as alternating daily between life and death, notably in Odyssey 11.302–304: οἳ καὶ νέρθεν γῆς τιμὴν πρὸς Ζηνὸς ἔχοντες/ἄλλοτε μὲν ζώουσ’ ἑτερήμεροι, ἄλλοτε δ’ αὖτε/ τεθνᾶσιν. The perspective of one twin being brought back to consciousness by the other—a one time event—is replaced by a daily alternation between the two states by both twins once they have changed from heroes into gods. The description above of the daily alternation between life and death of the Dioskouroi occurs in the catalogue of heroines encountered by Odysseus in the underworld. In this catalogue Leda, the mother of the Dioskouroi, is juxtaposed with Chloris, the mother of Nestor. The effect of this is to create an implicit contrast with Nestor’s version of the twin myth, in which he does not remain forever by his brother’s side but instead takes his brother’s place. Cf. HN 228–233 [§2.101–§2.103].
[ back ] 27. Archaic evidence for statues of the Dioskouroi’s sons Mnasínous and Anaxías connects the former with the immortal Polydeuces and the latter with Castor. Cf. HN 86–87 [§1.65] for both names. The name Mnasínous, containing the noun νόος, apparently means ‘he who remembers his nóos’, and it is hard to say what this would actually signify; the compound name seems intended simply to betoken ‘intelligence’ in both its elements, and this surely has to do with a quality of Polydeuces, the father of this ‘hyperintelligent’ son. Cf. HN 74–75 [§1.57] and 84–87 [§1.63–§1.65] for more on the ‘intelligence’ of Polydeuces as opposed to the warrior qualities of Castor.
[ back ] 28. There are three examples, the clearest of which is RV 8.22.17: ā́ no áśvāvad aśvinā /vartír yāsiṣṭam madhupātamā narā /gómad dasrā híraṇyavat, “Come to us (ā no … yāsiṣṭam) along the path (vartír) rich in horses, you Aśvinā; come, you who most enjoy the sacrificial drink, you heroes (madhupātamā narā); come along the path rich in cattle, you dasrā, rich in gold.” The verse’s two eight-syllable segments, the first segment and the last, articulate the oppositions in question by their parallel structure, while the middle segment differs in both length (eleven syllables) and structure. Cf. HN 67–71 [§1.52– §1.54].
[ back ] 29. For two striking examples, in Iliad 9.103–108 and Iliad 14.61–62, see HN 52–54 [§1.35– §1.36].
[ back ] 30. Menelaos calls on Antilochus to hold back until it is safe to pass, but Antilochus only drives on the harder, κέντρῳ ἐπισπέρχων ὡς οὐκ ἀΐοντι ἐοικώς, “laying on with the goad like one who does not hear” (23.430).
[ back ] 31. κέντρῳ in 23.430
[ back ] 32. The aged Nestor in the Odyssey thus acts out his name in terms of the synchronic meaning of nóstos, ‘return home’, rather than the diachronic meaning, ‘return to life’, but in the deep structure of the poem the two remain connected. Cf. n. 36 below.
[ back ] 33. Nestor connects the Iliad and the Odyssey as in effect one long poem in Iliad 8 in an episode that alludes directly to his role in Odyssey 3. He is the same character in both poems. Cf. HN Ch.6, 173–225 [§2.56– §2.99].
[ back ] 34. Menelaos had caught up with Nestor and Diomedes on Lesbos as they pondered their next decision, ὀψὲ δὲ δὴ μετὰ νῶϊ κίε ξανθὸς Μενέλαος,/ ἐν Λέσβῳ δ’ ἔκιχεν δολιχὸν πλόον ὁρμαίνοντας (“Long afterwards fair-haired Menelaos reached the two of us and found us in Lesbos pondering the long voyage,” 3.168–169).
[ back ] 35. There are telling examples in Iliad 2.350–353 and Iliad 15.379–380. Cf. HN 85–90 (§2.67).
[ back ] 36. The difference between the chariot race of the youthful Nestor and the return home from Troy of the aged Nestor reflects the evolution of Greek epic from its IE origins. In the IE myth the twins are youthful horsemen, as is the case of the Greek Dioskouroi, and of Nestor in his Homeric stories. In Nestor’s youthful chariot race the opposition between incitement and restraint is a step removed from the basic IE twin myth, where the oppositions are life and death, consciousness and unconsciousness. In Nestor’s chariot race these oppositions are only symbolized, death being represented by the turning post, a tomb. I speculate that the chariot race, with its opposition between restraint in rounding the turning post and incitement in reaching the final goal, goes back to IE. If so (but IE chariots remain a question), the role of νόος in Nestor’s youthful race also goes back to IE. The aged Nestor, on the other hand, is the product of Homeric epic in its monumental final phase. Thus the representation of νόος in his return from Troy, while it presupposes the word’s origin in the IE twin myth, also transcends this origin. It should be noted, however, that a νόστος, as it is represented in the story of Odysseus in the Odyssey, preserved strong associations with a ‘return to life’ from an earlier stage of epic. This point, which is relevant to Nestor’s role in the Odyssey as a νόστος poem, was the subject of my study, The Myth of Return in Early Greek Epic (New Haven 1978), online at http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Frame.The_Myth_of_Return_in_Early_Greek_Epic.1978.
[ back ] 37. As in the name Mnasínous ‘he who remembers his mind’, where noũs (nóos) is simply a common noun.
[ back ] 38. See HN 54 [§1.37], 244–254 [§2.110– §2.116].
 
νόος (nóos)
Greek nóos ‘mind’ (contracted form noũs) contains a verbal root. It has the same shape as such Greek nouns as lógos or phóbos, the verbal roots of which are clear: logos ‘word’ contains the root of légō ‘speak’, and phóbos ‘panic flight’ contains the root of phébomai ‘flee in panic’. By contrast the root of nóos is not clear because the second consonant of the root has dropped out between vowels and could have been three different things. The formal evidence points to the root *nes– insofar as the roots *new– and *ney– are both improbable. The classical Greek name Ἰφίνοος, a compound with the second element –noos, occurs in Mycenaean Greek as Wiphinoos (Linear B wi-pi-no-o). If this name is taken as evidence for the noun nóos, [1] the missing consonant cannot have been –w– as –w– was still preserved in Linear B, as in the first element Wiphi– of the Mycenaean name. The Mycenaean name does allow its second element –noos to be recontructed as original *-noyos insofar as –y-, unlike –w-, had already dropped out between vowels in Linear B. A verb with the root *ney– occurs in Sanskrit nayati ‘to lead’, but Greek has no trace of this verbal root. The Sankrit noun nayaḥ from the root of nayati ‘to lead’ means ‘conduct, management, policy, wisdom’, but a comparison with Greek nóos is illusory. The dictum to seek Latin etymologies on the Tiber should be followed in this case as the root *nes-, in contrast to *ney-, is abundantly attested in Greek. Like the consonant –y-, the consonant –s– had already dropped out between vowels in Linear B, and the Mycenaean name Wiphinoos can thus be reconstructed with confidence as earlier *Wiphinosos, with a trace of the lost –s– likely surviving as –h– in pronunciation, Wiphinohos, in Mycenaean Greek.
The Greek verb néomai ‘return home’ contains the verbal root *nes-. The –s– of the root has dropped out between vowels in néomai but is preserved in nóstos ‘return home’, a noun from this root. The root occurs in other Indo-European domains, principally Indic and Germanic. Sanskrit násate ‘resort to’ is an exact cognate of néomai, and various forms containing the root occur in the different branches of Germanic. Gothic ganisan and Modern High German genesen, both meaning ‘return to life, get well’, contain the root prefixed by a perfective element ga/ge. A causative form from the root is found in all three branches of Germanic: Gothic nasjan, Old English nerian, and Old Norse, nœra, all mean ‘save, bring back to life’; Modern High German nähren ‘feed’ shows a semantic development from these meanings.
To explain the noun nóos as a derivative of the root *nes– the semantics of the root in Indo-European and in Greek must be analyzed. “Revenir à un état familier,” Benveniste’s formulation for the Indo-European meaning of the root, [2] combines the notion of ‘return home’ of Greek néomai with a different sense of ‘return’ in the Germanic evidence, where ‘return’ is to a state, ‘life’, rather than to a place, ‘home’. The notion of ‘returning to life’, the basic meaning of the root in Germanic, can also be demonstrated for the Greek root in the traditional diction of Greek epic, where “returning home” implies “returning to life” in a demonstrably old Homeric formula. In the thrice-repeated formula ἄσμενοι ἐκ θανάτοιο the form ἄσμενοι is to be reconstructed as a root aorist participle of néomai with zero-grade of the root (*ṇs-menoi), and the formula means literally “having returned from death.” In the context of Odysseus’s adventures in the Odyssey, where this formula caps three adventures in which some of the hero’s men perish and the others are saved, a “return from death” is recast as an “escape from death.” The stronger sense of a “return from death,” which the formula expressed in earlier epic tradition, bears comparison with the meaning “return to life” of the Germanic evidence. [3] The notion of a return to a place in néomai ‘return home’ is also old, as the Sanskrit evidence attests. While násate ‘resort to’ is bleached in meaning, it shows that physical movement was implied in the IE verb from which the Greek and Sanskrit verbs descend; even the notion of a “return home” can be reconstructed for IE on the basis of a Sanskrit noun with zero-grade of the root *nes-, namely astam ‘home’ from *ṇs-to.
In sum, the line between the notions of returning to a place and returning to a state may not have been sharply drawn in Indo-European, especially in the domain of myth and poetics. In Germanic the notion of a state predominates, whereas in Greek a place and a state continue to coexist in the meaning of the root, although the notion of a state (“life”) has faded by the time of Homeric epic.
If “return” was the basic notion of the root of nóos the noun most likely designated “consciousness” in the first place. [4] Waking and sleeping are a daily alternation between consciousness and unconsciousness, and unconsciousness also characterizes the dead in ancient myth: among the dead only Teiresias, the exception to the rule, has nóos in the Odyssey: τῷ καὶ τεθνηῶτι νόον πόρε Περσεφόνεια / οἴῳ πεπνῦσθαι· τοὶ δὲ σκιαὶ ἀΐσσουσιν (10.494–495). “Consciousness” is a “return to life,” whether for one and all each morning, or from the realm of the dead in the context of myth and ritual. [5]
“Consciousness” seems a satisfactory notion for what nóos originally designated, but it leaves unanswered the exact semantics of nóos as a verbal noun. Was nóos simply a ‘returning’ in contrast to ‘nóstos’, a ‘return’? Or was there a sharper semantic distinction between the two nouns? The Homeric figure Nestor, whose name contains the root *nes-, is the key to this question. The name Νέστωρ is discussed in a separate CIGE entry.
 
Douglas Frame, 2020.11.11
 
[ back ] 1. For more on the relationship of the name Wiphinoos to the noun nóos, see CIGE s.v. Νέστωρ.
[ back ] 2. É. Benveniste, Problems de linguistique générale (Paris 1966) 172.
[ back ] 3. In the Gothic bible of Ulfilas ganisan translates σώζεσθαι ‘be saved’ in the context of Christian salvation. Modern High German genesen occurs in a similar context in this example from J. S. Bach’s Cantata 31 (libretto Solomon Franck): “Adam muß in uns verwesen, / Soll der neue Mensch genesen, /Der nach Gott geschaffen ist./Du mußt geistlich auferstehen/Und aus Sündengräbern gehen,/Wenn du Christi Gliedmaß bist.”
The opposition between verwesen ‘perish’ and genesen ‘come back to life’ is striking.
[ back ] 4. For nóos as ‘consciousness’, cf. my Hippota Nestor (Cambridge, MA and Washington, DC: 2009) 93–94 [§1.69]; online http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Frame.Hippota_Nestor.2009.
[ back ] 5. The meaning of the IE root *nes– was not only ‘return to life’, but also ‘return to the light’, and the context for such a combined ‘return to life and light’ was solar myth. The relevance of solar myth to the Odyssey as a nostos poem was explored in my Myth of Return in Early Greek Epic (New Haven 1978); online http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Frame.The_Myth_of_Return_in_Early_Greek_Epic.1978. A solar context fits well with nóos as ‘consciousness’ in a daily alternation with ‘unconsciousness’. Cf. the CIGE entry Νέστωρ for further focus on such a daily alternation in relation to nóos and the root *nes-.
 
῞Ομηρος (Hómēros)
A. Etymologically, the form is a compound *hóm-āros meaning ‘he who fits / joins together’, composed of the prefix homo– ‘together’ and the root of the verb arariskein (ἀρ-αρ-ίσκειν) ‘fit, join’. So Hómēros is ‘he who fits [the song] together’.
Nagy emphasizes the importance of the word kúklos in building a metaphorical relationship between Homeric poetry, the epic cycle, and the master-carpenter, téktōn. Thus “the etymology of Hómēros, in the sense of ‘fitting together’, is an aspect of this metaphor: a master poet ‘fits together’ pieces of poetry that are made ready to be parts of an integrated whole just as a master carpenter or joiner ‘fits together’ or ‘joins’ pieces of wood that are made ready to be parts of a chariot wheel.”
B. “The etymology of the noun hómēros (ὅμηρος) … [has] the sense of ‘hostage’, which derives from the same compound *hóm-āros meaning ‘he who fits / joins together’.” (2§331)
Further, “a hostage is the visible sign of a pact or agreement between two parties, that is, of a ‘joining together’ or ‘bonding’. Such a meaning evidently derives from metaphors of social bonding inherent in derivatives of ararískein (ἀρ-αρ-ίσκειν) ‘fit, join’: an ideal case in point is arthmós (ἀρθμός) ‘bond, league, friendship’ and related forms. The etymology of the noun hómēros (ὅμηρος) in the sense of ‘hostage’ is in turn compatible in meaning with the etymology of the verb homēreîn/ homēreúein (ὁμηρεῖν / ὁμηρεύειν) in the sense of ‘joining’ the company of someone or ‘accompanying’ someone.” (2§332)
Nagy, G. 2012. “Further Variations on a Theme of Homer.” Chapter 9 of Homer the Preclassic. Berkeley. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Homer_the_Preclassic.2009.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Emma Brobeck 2015.11.05
C. The reconstructed noun *hóm-āros can be interpreted as a compound formation meaning ’he who fits [the song] together’, composed of the prefix homo– (ὁμο-) ‘together’ and the root ar– of the verb ararískein (ἀραρίσκειν). As we see from a survey of the oldest attested formations involving the root ar-, this form expresses primarily the idea of woodwork and secondarily the idea of other handicrafts that involve the fitting together of distinct pieces into a unified whole. Moreover, this form extends metaphorically to the art of songmaking. The name Hómēros in its traditional contexts is linked to all these meanings. The name means literally ‘joiner’ or ‘carpenter’. So, etymologically, Hómēros is a master joiner of woodwork; and, metaphorically, Homer is a master joiner of song. (2§282 )
Nagy, G. 2009. “Homer the Classic in the Age of Callimachus.” Chapter 2 of Homer the Classic. Washington, DC. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Homer_the_Classic.2008.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Milan Vidaković, 2105.11.06
ποικίλος/ποικίλλειν (poikílos/poikíllein)
The adjective poikílos, Nagy argues, generally means ‘varied’, with the specialized meaning ‘pattern-woven’. It is closely related to the verb poikíllein, which means ‘pattern-weave’. The noun poikílma is also derived from the verb poikíllein ’pattern-weave’, and refers to fabric that is “woven … rather than embroidered.” Nagy cites the following comparative evidence for interpreting poikíllein as referring to pattern-weaving: “The verb poikíllein itself, along with the adjective poikílos, meaning ‘varied’, is derived from the root *peik-, also attested in Latin pictūra. So poikíllein means literally ‘make (things) be poikíla’, that is, ‘make (things) be varied’. These words poikílos and poikíllein convey not only the general idea of variation. They convey also the specific idea of a picture, whether static or moving: in fact, they are cognate with the Latin word pictūra. This word evokes for us the celebrated formulation ut pictūra poesis ‘like the painting is the poetry’ in Horace’s Ars Poetica (Epistulae 2.3.361).” In applying this etymology to the epithet of Aphrodite, poikilóthronos (Sappho Song 1.1), Nagy understands Aphrodite poikilothronos as ‘Our Lady of the varied pattern-woven floral love charms’.
Nagy, G. 2009. “Homer the Classic in the Age of Virgil.” Chapter 1 of Homer the Classic. Washington, DC. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Homer_the_Classic.2008.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Eunice Kim, 2015.11.05
πολυδευκής (poludeukḗs)
The starting point for this examination of poludeukḗs is Odyssey 19.520, where the nightingale is described as follows:

 

ἥ τε θαμὰ τρωπῶσα χέει πολυηχέα φωνήν
and she pours forth, changing it around thick and fast, a voice with many resoundings,
Aelian in De natura animalium (5.38) records a variant reading “poludeukḗs as an alternative to poluēkhés ‘with many resoundings’ in Odyssey 19 (521) and glosses it as τὴν ποικίλως μεμιμημένην ‘making imitation [mimesis] in a varied [poikílōs] way’. Aelian is interested mainly in the nightingale’s versatility as an imitator, but the epithet poludeukḗa draws attention also to the continuity of the singer’s performance.
If indeed poludeukḗs implies that the nightingale is τὴν ποικίλως μεμιμημένην ‘the one who makes imitation [mimesis] in a varied [ poikílōs ] way’, then this variant epithet poludeukḗs points to the songbird’s capacity for variety. But there is even more to Aelian’s description of the nightingale’s birdsong, since he insists on the notion of mimesis in his definition: τὴν ποικίλως μεμιμημένην ‘the one who makes imitation [mimesis] in a varied [poikílōs] way’. If Aelian is right, then the variant epithet poludeukḗs conveys not only variety but also the very idea of mimesis, which is translated here as ‘imitation’. If he is right, then poludeukḗs is closely parallel in meaning to poluēkhḗs ‘with many resoundings’, since ēkhṓ ‘resounding, echo’ likewise conveys the idea of mimesis. Moreover, there is a deeper meaning of mimesis, which can be understood by discovering the deeper meaning of the epithet poludeukḗs.
Pierre Chantraine in his Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque and Ernst Risch in his Wortbildung der homerischen Sprache are both uncertain about how to explain the meaning of the root *deuk / *duk in poludeukḗs, but they are both quite certain about the morphological relationship of this word with two other words, the negative adeukḗs and the adverb endukéōs. Aelian as well, in his discussion of poludeukḗs as an epithet of the nightingale, treats adeukḗs as the negative of poludeukḗs. He thinks that adeukḗs means ‘incapable of mimesis’. The word mimesis in such a context means more than ‘imitation’: it conveys also a deeper sense of continuity.
Another related word is endukéōs, which is associated with the notion of an uninterrupted sequence, as for example in contexts like the verse in Odyssey xiv (337) involving the action of sending or accompanying someone on a journey (verb pémpein at 333, 334, 338). Conversely, the negative adeukḗs occurs in contexts referring to an interrupted sequence, as in a quoted question about the Achaeans coming home from Troy in Odyssey 4 (489).
The words poludeukḗs, adeukḗs and endukéōs “are all derived from the same root *deuk / *duk that we find in Latin dūcere, dux.”
In their etymological dictionary of Latin, Ernout and Meillet explain dūcere as an old pastoral word conveying the basic idea of pull rather than push (agere): the herdsman or dux is “pulling” or leading (dūcere) the herd when he goes in front, while he is “pushing” or driving (agere) when he is coming up from behind. Going beyond this formulation of Ernout and Meillet, Emile Benveniste adds the notion of a continuum, so that the dux who marches in front of the aggregate is necessarily connected, as the prime linking force, as it were, to the train that follows.
The Latin expression “fīlum dēdūcere ‘draw out a thread [in spinning]’ (e.g. Ovid Metamorphoses 4.36; cf. Tibullus 1.3.86)” is comparable to places where the verbs dūcere or dēdūcere are “metaphorically combined with objects like carmen ‘song’ to mean ‘compose the song’ (e.g. Propertius 4.6.13, Ovid Metamorphoses 1.4).
The association of the root *deuk / *duk with the idea of songmaking takes us back to the meaning of poludeukḗs, variant epithet for the nightingale’s song in Odyssey 19 (521), which we may now interpret as meaning ‘having much continuity’ or ‘having continuity in many different ways’ or even ‘patterning in many ways’ (or ‘many times’). The translation ‘patterning’ highlights the idea of continuity through variety and diversity. And the patterns of continuity through variety and diversity are conceived as the distinctly poetic skills of songmaking in performance. Morevoer, the idea of ‘many different ways’ (or ‘many times’) is an inherently agonistic one, with each new performance ever competing against previous performances. Thus poludeukḗs in the sense of ‘patterning in many different ways’ (or ‘many times’) is an apt description of oral tradition itself.”
Nagy, G. 1996. “The Homeric Nightingale and the Poetics of Variation in the Art of a Troubadour” and “Mimesis, Models of Singers, and the Meaning of a Homeric Epithet.” Chapters 1 and 2 of Poetry as Performance: Homer and Beyond. Cambridge. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Poetry_as_Performance.1996.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Edgar A. García 2015.12.10 and Olga Levaniouk 2016.01.19
ποταμός (Potamós)
The Greek term potamós ‘river’ (Iliad and elsewhere) is also attested as the name of the deified Rivers (e.g., Hesiod Theogony 337) who are born from the cosmic river Ocean and the deity Tethys (on which see further Tēthū́s). The etymology of potamós is still controversial: it has been traced back to several different Indo-European roots, including *peth1 ‘fall’ (LIV2:477-478), *peth2 ‘extend’ (LIV2:478-479), and *peth2 ‘fly’ (LIV2:479). The latter etymology (from ‘fly’) may indeed find some support in the Indo-European image of the “flying rivers” (cf. Schmitt 1967: 221-236), while the second one (from ‘extend’) has more recently been argued for by Michael Janda (2005:238-249). None of these fascinating proposals seems to have gained wide acceptance yet (cf. Frisk 1960-1972: 585-586; DELG:931; Beekes 2010: 1225-1226), probably because they all involve Indo-European roots whose semantic connection with water is not very straightforward.
A new etymological connection with the Indo-European root *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’ is pursued in Ginevra 2020, on which this entry is based. This root is attested, for example, by the Vedic Sanskrit participle kváth-ant- ‘foaming, seething’ and the Gothic verb ƕaþjan* ‘to foam, ἀφρίζειν’, and is currently reconstructed as *ku̯ath2 (LIV2: 374), with -a- vocalism, a reconstruction that, however, relies on the highly problematic (Schrijver 1991:251-252) connection with Latin cāseus ‘cheese’, and should thus be dropped in favor of the a more regular shape *ku̯eth2. As argued below, Greek potamós ‘river’ may be a reflex of the root *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’ either as an inherited primary adjective or as an inner-Greek denominative formation.
According to the first possibility, pota-mós may be the expected outcome of *ku̯oth2-mó- ‘foamy, foaming, seething’, a primary adjective of *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’, of the same type ([C]CoC[C]-mó-) as the inherited adjective *gu̯hor-mό- ‘warm’ (root *gu̯her- ‘be/become warm’, cf. LIV2:219-220) that underlies Vedic gharmá- ‘heat’ (substantivization), Lat. formus ‘warm’, as well as the Germanic reflexes of *warma- ‘heat’, including Old English wearm, the ancestor of English warm; as for Greek thermos, it is the reflex of a likely innovative formation *gu̯her-mό- (on the vocalism of which, see Probert 2006:242).
If its original meaning was ‘foamy, foaming, seething’, potamós would thus reflect a so-called “transferred epithet” (Watkins 1995: 156) of rivers, i.e., a designation which may be originally traced back to a traditional epithet, as in the case of Vedic Pr̥thivī́- ‘Earth’, used as a common noun, which literally means ‘the Broad One’, being the feminine of the adjective pr̥thú- ‘broad’.
Alternatively, pot-amós ‘river’ (with different morphological segmentation) may have been derived within Greek itself from either *pót-ο- ‘foam’ or *pot-ā́- ‘foam’ by means of a secondary suffix -amos. This derivational process is for instance attested by Homeric plók-amos ‘lock of hair’ (from plók-os ‘lock of hair, wreath’ or plok-ḗ ‘lock of hair’) and órkh-amos ‘chief, ruler’ (which may be derived from *orkh-ā́, possibly attested by Myc. o-ka, if it reflects /orkh-ā-/ ‘command’, related to árkh-ō ‘to rule’; however, a different interpretation as /ōg-ā́-/, related to ag-ōg-ḗ ‘act of leading, guidance’ and ág-ō ‘lead’ is proposed by Vine 1998: 698-699).
If potamós indeed reflects such a derivative, the underlying noun *pót-ο- ‘foam’ may have been the outcome of *ku̯óth2-o- ‘foam, seething’, a noun of the type of Greek tóm-o-s ‘cutting’, whereas the alternative derivational base *pot-ā́- ‘id.’ may reflect *ku̯oth2-éh2, which may either be a noun of the type of Greek tom-ḗ ‘cutting’ or a collective derivative of *ku̯óth2-o-. The absence of aspiration of *-t- before *-h2, though problematic, has a parallel in the widely accepted correspondence between Greek platús ‘wide, broad’ and Vedic pr̥thú- ‘id.’ (both reflexes of *pl̥th2-u-; for an overview of scholarly theories, see de Decker 2016:98-101). Originally, Greek pot-amós may thus have had the same semantics ‘foam’ as its derivational basis *pót-ο- or *pot-ā́-, as in the case of plók-amos ‘lock of hair’; alternatively, it may have also had an original possessive meaning ‘having foam’, as it is probably the case of órkh-amos ‘chief, ruler’, originally ‘having command’ (if it is indeed related to Myc. o-ka ‘command’).
This reconstruction would find a close match in the reconstructed noun *hwaþ-a- ‘foam’ that underlies various Germanic formations, such as Gothic ƕaþjan* ‘to foam’, the likely reflex of a denominative verb *hwaþ-ja- derived from a noun *hwaþ-a- ‘foam’; the same derivational type is attested, for instance, by the ancestor of English deem, the reconstructed verb *dōm-ija- ‘to deem’ from *dōm-a- ‘judgement’ (Ringe 2006: 254), whereas the alternative analysis (LIV2: 374) of Gothic ƕaþjan* as a reflex of a causative/iterative formation *ku̯oth2-éi̯e- is impossible because of the so-called “Verner‘s Law” (by which an Indo-European root’s *t followed by a stressed syllable should be reflected by a Germanic *d). This is highly relevant to the present discussion, because the reconstructed noun *hwaþ-a- ‘foam’ underlying Gothic ƕaþjan* ‘to foam’ may not only serve as a possible derivational basis for the feminine noun *hwaþ-ō (n) ‘foam’ which underlies both Gothic ƕaþo ‘foam’ and Swedish kva ‘foam’, but also be a reflex of the same noun *ku̯óth2-o- ‘foam’ reconstructed above for Greek *πότ-ο- ‘id.’.
If no alternatives were available, the analysis of Greek pot-amós as a derivative of *pót-ο- ‘foam’ would thus be supported in the lexicon of another Indo-European branch, the Germanic one. The accentuation of potamós, however, seems to support the first analysis presented here, namely as the reflex of a primary adjective *ku̯oth2-mó- ‘foamy, foaming, seething’: oxytone accentuation is consistent among Greek primary -mό- adjectives (such as thermós ‘warm’, ōmós ‘raw’, and dokhmós ‘slant’) and likely to be an inherited feature (being paralleled by that of their Sanskrit cognates), whereas secondary formations with suffix -amos are expected to have recessive accent in Ancient Greek (Probert 2006: 240). A secondary inner-Greek formation derived from *pót-ο- ‘foam’ should thus have been pótamos or the like, matching plókamos and órkhamos.
As for the semantics, the development from a primary adjective *ku̯oth2-mó- ‘foamy, foaming, seething’ to Greek potamós ‘river’ finds support in the (fairly trivial) traditional association of the rivers, the ocean, and bodies of water in general with foaming and seething, which is for instance attested in Homeric Greek by the formulaic expression aphrō̂i mormúrōn “seething with foam”, always referring to either rivers or the ocean in Homeric poetry:

ὡς δ’ ὅτ’ ἀνὴρ ἀπάλαμνος ἰὼν πολέος πεδίοιο
στήῃ ἐπ’ ὠκυρόῳ ποταμῷ ἅλαδε προρέοντι
ἀφρῷ μορμύροντα ἰδών, ἀνά τ’ ἔδραμ’ ὀπίσσω,
“[…] and just as a man in passing over a great plain halts helpless at a swift-streaming river that flows on to the sea, and seeing it seething with foam starts backward”
Iliad 5.597-599
[…] περὶ δὲ ῥόος Ὠκεανοῖο
ἀφρῷ μορμύρων ῥέεν ἄσπετος· […]
“[…] and round about me flowed the stream of Oceanus, seething with foam, a flood unspeakable”
Iliad 18.402-403
Ἦ, καὶ ἐπῶρτ’ Ἀχιλῆϊ κυκώμενος ὑψόσε θύων
μορμύρων ἀφρῷ τε καὶ αἵματι καὶ νεκύεσσι. 
“He (the river Skamandros) spoke, and rushed tumultuously on Achilles, raging on high and seething with foam and blood and corpses”
Iliad 21.324-325
The association of rivers with foaming and seething is also, of course attested in texts from other Indo-European traditions, such as the works of Latin authors Vergil and Lucan and the Indic Rigveda:

non sic, aggeribus ruptis cum spumeus amnis
exiit oppositasque evicit gurgite moles
“Not with such fury, when a foaming river, bursting its barriers, has overflowed and with its torrent overwhelmed the resisting banks […]”
Vergil Aeneid 2.496
Cuncta fremunt undis, ac multo murmure montis
Spumeus invitis canescit fluctibus amnis.
“The region roars with his waves, the cliff rumbles loudly, and the foamy river whitens under the constraint of his flood”
Lucan Bellum Civile 10.321-322
krátuṃ rihanti mádhunābhí añjate
síndhor ucchvāsé patáyantam ukṣáṇaṃ
“They lick (him who is) resolve; they anoint him with honey – him, the ox flying in the burbling up of the river
RV 9.86.43bc
ū́rṇāvatī yuvatíḥ sīlámāvatī
“The young woman (= the river Sindhu) is rich in wool (= foam), in sīlamā (plants?)”
RV 10.75.8ac
As for the association of foaming and seething with the ocean and with other bodies of water correspondences may be found, for instance, in Vedic itself and in two Germanic traditions, namely in Old Norse and in Old English. The development of an adjective ‘foamy’ into a term referring to a body of water proposed above for potamós may have parallels in Vedic and Old Norse, if Stephanie Jamison is correct in assuming that Vedic ārjīkī́ya- ‘foamy’ refers to a ‘lake’ in the first passage below from the Rigveda, matching the second passage below from a Norse skaldic poem, where Old Norse lauðr ‘foam, surf’ is used to refer to the ‘sea’ in general:

ayáṃ te śaryaṇā́vati
suṣómāyām ádhi priyáḥ
ārjīkī́ye madíntamaḥ
“Here is your dear (soma) in the reed-filled (pond?), here in the Suṣomā (River?) the most invigorating in the foamy (lake?)
RV 8.64.11
Veðr blæss vegg of tyggja;
viðr þolir nauð í lauðri
“The storm-wind fills the sail above the sovereign; the timber (= ship) suffers distress in the foam (= sea)
Lausavísur from Magnúss saga berfœtts 6 1-2
Finally, the association between a reflex of the root *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’ and bodies of water ocean is etymologically supported by Old English phraseology, which attests a verbal formation of this very root (cf. Kroonen 2013: 264), namely hwaþerian / hwoþerian ‘to foam, seethe, roar’, whose usual subject is precisely the ‘sea’, as in the two passages below:

[…] Se brym hwoðerode under his fotswaðum […]
The sea foamed / seethed / roared under his footsteps”
ÆCHom II, 28
[…] þæt gewealc þara yða hwaðerode mid windum […]
the tumult of the waves roared with the winds”
ApT 11
Whatever the details of its etymological analysis, from a semantic perspective Greek potamós ‘river’ may thus be easily traced back to the root *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’, the same root that may also underlie the name of the mother of all deified Rivers, on which see further Tēthū́s.
[Translations of Classical sources are adapted from the Loeb Classical Library. Translations of other sources are adapted from:
Gade, K. 2009. Anonymous Lausavísur, Lausavísur from Magnúss saga berfœtts 6. In Poetry from the Kings’ Sagas 2: From c. 1035 to c. 1300, ed. K. E. Gade, 833-834. Turnhout: Brepols.
Jamison, S. W., and J. Brereton. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.]
Beekes, R. 2010. Etymological Dictionary of Greek. Leiden & Boston: Brill.
De Decker, F. 2016 [2015]. “What Is the Greek Counterpart of (Proto-)Indo-Iranian (*) th?” International Journal of Diachronic Linguistics and Linguistic Reconstruction 12:89-164.
DELG = Pierre Chantraine. 1968-1980. Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque. Paris: Klincksieck.
Frisk, H. 1960-1972. Griechisches Etymologisches Wörterbuch. Heidelberg: Winter.
Ginevra, R. 2020. “Foamy Rivers and the Wife of the Ocean: Greek ποταμός ‘river’, Τηθῡ́ς ‘mother of all rivers’, and Proto-Indo-European *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’.” In Papers on Ancient Greek Linguistics. Proceedings of the Ninth International Colloquium on Ancient Greek Linguistics (ICAGL 9), 30 August – 1 September 2018, Helsinki, eds. M. Leiwo, M. Vierros, and S. Dahlgren, 99-110. Helsinki.
Janda, M. 2005. Elysion. Entstehung und Entwicklung der griechischen Religion. Innsbruck: Institut für Sprachen und Literaturen der Universität Innsbruck.
LIV2 = Helmut Rix (ed.). 2001. Lexikon der indogermanischen Verben. Wiesbaden: Reichert.
Kroonen, G. 2013. Etymological Dictionary of Proto-Germanic. Leiden: Brill.
Probert, P. 2006. Ancient Greek Accentuation. Synchronic Patterns, Frequency Effects, and Prehistory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ringe, D. 2006. A Linguistic History of English I. From Proto-Indo-European to Proto-Germanic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schmitt, R. 1967. Dichtung und Dichtersprache in indogermanischer Zeit. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz.
Schrijver, P. 1991. The reflexes of the Proto-Indo-European laryngeals in Latin. Amsterdam & Atlanta: Rodopi.
Vine, B. 1998. “The Etymology of Greek κώμη and Related Problems.” In Mír Curad: Studies in Honor of Calvert Watkins, eds. Jay Jasanoff, H. Craig Melchert, and Lisi Olivier, 685-702. Innsbruck: Institut für Sprachwissenschaft der Universität Innsbruck.
Watkins, C. 1995. How to Kill a Dragon: Aspects of Indo-European Poetics. New York & Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 
Riccardo Ginevra, 2022.10.25
Προμηθεύς and Ἐπιμηθεύς (Promētheús and Epimētheús)
The earliest attestation of the myth about Promētheús (Προμηθεύς) and Epimētheús (Ἐπιμηθεύς) is in Hesiodic poetry: Theogony (507–616) and Works and Days (47–105), on which see the rich analysis by Vernant (1974:103–120, 177–194, commented by Nagy 1990:80–81). The story goes that Promētheús tricked Zeus on the occasion of a proto-sacrificial division of the meat of a slaughtered ox. He wrapped the ox’s meat in its hide, while he covered the bones of the animal in fat. After choosing the heap covered in fat, Zeus realized that the Titan had tricked him. As a consequence, he decided to conceal fire from the mortal men. But Promētheús stole it from Zeus and bestowed it to humanity. This time, Zeus ordered to Hephaestus to mold a beautiful virgin, whom the Olympians adorned with all gifts, Pandora. Despite the warnings of his brother Promētheús, Epimētheús decided to open the lid of Pandora’s box, which released all sorts of woes for the mortal men.
According to ancient commentators, the name Promētheús was related to the Greek adjective promēthḗs (προμηθής) ‘forethinking’ and to the verb promanthánō (προμανθάνω) ‘to learn in advance’. As such, the name Promētheús is the exact opposite of his brother’s, Epimētheús, which is connected with the verb epimanthánō (ἐπιμανθάνω) ‘to learn after’. In contrasting “artful and wily Promētheús” and “defective in his thinking Epimētheús” as Hesiodic poetry retains a reflex of the synchronic etymology of the terms:

 

Τίκτε δ ὑπερκύδαντα Μενοίτιον ἠδὲ Προμηθέα
ποικίλον αἰολόμητιν, ἀμαρτίνοόν τ᾽ Ἐπιμηθέα

 

Hesiod Theogony 510–511
She (Kluménē) gave birth to very glorious Meoítios and Promētheús, artful and full of many wiles, and Epimētheús, defective in his thinking
Although the names ‘Forethought’ and ‘Afterthought’ suit the two brothers, who display opposite intellectual qualities, it is likely that the name Promētheús has a different etymology and that the connection with both promanthánō and Epimētheús are secondary developments which took place within Greek.
It has long been proposed that the name of Greek Promētheús is etymologically related to Sanskrit pramantha– ‘fire-drill’ (Kuhn 1886:17–8), a nominal derivative to the same Vedic root as manthi ‘to churn, to rub’, which goes back to the Indo-European root *menth2 ‘to churn, to rub’. Vedic manthi commonly applies to the production of fire in both the Rigveda and late Vedic texts: as pointed out by Nagy 1990:105, Mātariśvan, the Vedic fire-thief, produces fire by friction, a ritual gesture commonly reproduced in the Vedic fire-sacrifice, compare the collocation agním manthāma ‘let us rub fire’ (Rigveda 3.29.1d). However, despite the meaning and collocations of Vedic manthi and pramantha-, which would be highly compatible with the role of Promētheús in Greek, the two terms are phonologically incompatible with the Greek name: it is impossible to derive a basis *pro-māth (Greek Προμηθεύς, Thessalian Προμᾱθεύς) from a root *menth2. The coincidence between Promētheús and pramantha– ‘fire-drill’ can therefore be classified as a Scheingleichung, that is to say, as an ‘apparent/superficial coincidence’ which can be proved as false through the analysis of the linguistic details.
The name of Promētheús can actually be traced back to an Indo-European verbal root *math2 ‘to rob’, which underlies Vedic mathi ‘to rob’. The past participle mathitá- happens to be identical to the one of Vedic manthi ‘to rub’, which opens to a palette of different interpretations in the passages involving the fire-theft episode: take, for instance, the final phrase of Rigveda 3.9: devébhyo mathitám pári, which, as noticed by Jamison – Brereton (2014:481), “is translated ‘stolen from among the gods,’ could also mean ‘churned from among the gods.’” As Narten (1960:132–135) firstly pointed out, in the Rigveda, Vedic mathi describes the main achievement of the fire-thief Mātariśvan, who is the Vedic counterpart of Promētheús:

 

máthīd yád īṃ viṣṭó mātaríśvā
hótāraṃ viśvā́ápsuṃ viśvádevyam
ní yáṃ dadhúr manuṣíyā̀su vikṣú
súvàr ṇá citráṃ vápuṣe vibhā́vam

 

Rigveda 1.148.1, trans. Jamison – Brereton 2014
Since with effort Mātariśvan stole him, the Hotar bringing all goods (: Agni, the fire-god), belonging to all the gods, whom they installed for wonder among the clans of the sons of Manu, dazzling like the sun, far-radiant.

More specifically, since Greek names in -eús usually pair with names in -o-, just as in the case of hippeús ‘horseman’ and híppos ‘horse’ (Schindler 1976), a name Pro-mētheús might have paired with a form reconstructable as *pro-māthó- a derivative with lengthened a-grade to the root *math2 ‘to rob’ (see Oettinger 2016), underlying the Sanskrit term pramātha– ‘theft’. The very same root may underlie the name of another Old Indic fire-thief. As firstly suggested by Fay (1904:155), in the Śatapatha-Brāhmaṇa (1.4.1.10-21), Agni is said to have been carried in the mouth of King Māthava, who accidentally let him flash out in pronouncing the word for ‘ghee.’ The name Māthava, who acts as a ‘fire-concealer’ in the Vedic episode, could be a further Old Indic congener of Greek Promētheús (Gotō 2000:110, 2014:241).

As for Greek *Promātheus / *Promētheus, although the outcome -th notated 〈θ〉 from a sequence *-th2 (like in Indo-European *math2) is apparently problematic in Greek, the synchronic etymology of the Titan’s name as ‘Forethought’ may have played a role in reshaping *Promāteus (the putative outcome of *pro-māth2) to *Promātheus / *Promētheus (Massetti 2018:155).
In conclusion, the data from Indo-European phraseology show that Promētheús is the ‘Thief’ by name. However, his name was re-interpreted as ‘Forethought’ in Greek. The analysis additionally allows us to establish a relative chronology for the creation of the brother of Promētheús, Epimētheús ‘Afterthought’. This character must have entered Greek myth after the name of Promētheús had come to be perceived by the Greek speakers as ‘Mr. Forethought’.
Fay, E. W. 1904. “Prometheus in India.” Zeitschrift für vergleichende Sprachforschung auf dem Gebiete der Indogermanischen Sprachen 37:154–155.
Gotō, T. 2000. “Purūrávas und Urvaśī.” In Anusantatyai: Festschrift für Johanna Narten, eds. Helmut Hintze and Eva Tichy, 79–110. Dettelbach.
Gotō, T. 2014. “Hintergrund der indoarischen Einwanderung in Indien und die Menschengeschichte.” Journal of International Philosophy 3:231–248.
Jamison, S. W., and J. P. Brereton, trans. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. 3 vols. Oxford.
Kuhn, A. 1859. Mythologischen Studien. Vol. 1, Die Herabkunft des Feuers und des Göttertranks: ein Beitrag zur vergleichenden Mythologie der Indogermanen. Gurtersloh.
Massetti, L. 2018. “Another avatar of Mātariśvan? On the Hesychian Gloss Ἴθας, Ἴθαξ (Hsch. ι 387 L).” In Proceedings of the 28th Annual UCLA Indo-European Conference (Los Angeles), eds. David M. Goldstein, Stephanie W. Jamison, Brent Vine, 147–162. Bremen.
Narten, J. 1960. “Das vedische Verbum math.Indo-Iranian Journal 4:121–135.
Oettinger, N. 2016. “Zu gr. Prometheus, ved. Mātariśvan, Vivasvant, Yama und Manu.” International Journal of Diachronic Linguistics and Linguistic Reconstruction 13:233–246.
Schindler, J. 1976. “On Greek type ἱππεύς’.” In Studies in Greek, Italic and Indo-European Linguistics on the Occasion of his seventieth birthday June 5, 1976, eds. Anna Morpurgo Davies and Wolfgang Meid, 349–352. Innsbruck.
Vernant, J.-P. 1974. Mythe et société en Grèce ancienne. Paris.
 
Laura Massetti, 2020.03.31
σῆμα (sêma)
Brugmann’s etymology of the word sēma ‘sign’ connects it to the Indic dhyāma ‘thought’ (Brugmann 1886–1900 2:348); the forms would then reflect an Indo-European *dhiéh2–mn- (Beekes 2010 s.v.). Nagy supports Brugmann’s etymology (Greek Mythology and Poetics Chapter 8):

 

“The basic form in Greek is sēma ’sign’, a neuter action-noun built on a root-verb that is no longer attested in the language. There is a cognate of Greek sēma in the Indic branch of the Indo-European linguistic family. The form is dhyāma ’thought’, a neuter action-noun, attested only in the late Indic lexicographical tradition. This poorly attested noun is built on a root-verb that is well attested in early Indic. The root is dhyā– ‘think’ (variant of dhī– ‘think’). Even though the morphological relationship of dhyā– and dhyāma is transparent in Indic, and even though Indic dhyāma and Greek sêma would have to be considered cognates on the basis of their parallelism on the level of morphology, students of language are troubled by the apparent lack of parallelism on the level of semantics: how could the meaning ‘sign’ of Greek sēma be connected with the meaning ‘thought’ of Indic dhyāma?” (202)
Nagy thus endeavors “to show that the semantics of sêma are indeed connected with the semantics of thinking” by examining the word “not only in context but also specifically in the contexts of its behavior within the formulaic systems of archaic Greek poetic diction” (202), namely, by considering its relationship to the noun nóos ’mind, sense, perception’, and the derivative verb noéō ’perceive, take note, think, think through’ (203).
Nagy adduces a number of literary examples to demonstrate that in Greek, a sēma serves as a key to recognition, that recognition requires interpretation, and that nóos is the Greek word expressing the “basic faculty of recognition and interpretation” (204). For example, before the chariot race in the funeral games of Patroklos in Book 23 of the Iliad, Nestor gives his son Antilokhos a sign (sêma) when he gives him advice about how to win the chariot race, a sign which Antilokhos understands: “Antilokhos himself uses the verb noéō to express what he is doing (νοήσω 415). What, then, makes Nestor’s sēma work as a key to victory? It is the ability of his son to recognize how the sēma works within its code, which is equated with simply noticing it. And the word for this noticing/recognition is noéō” (209). Nestor’s advice is to turn as closely as possible to the térma ’turning point’ (Iliad 23.327–345), which he says is either the “tomb [sēma] of a man who died a long time ago, or it was a turning post in the times of earlier men” (Iliad 23.331–332) (215). Nagy connects the meaning of sēma ’tomb’ with the meaning ‘sign’: “As a ‘sign’ of the dead hero, the ‘tomb’ is a reminder of the hero and his kléos” (216).
The associations between the meanings of sēma lead Nagy to a discussion of Douglas Frame’s (1978) etymology of the word nóos: “The question is: what do these associations of sêma have to do with the semantics of nóos? As Frame argues in the course of his illuminating hook, nóos is an action-noun derived from the Indo-European root-verb *nes– meaning ‘return to light and life’. . . . The root-verb *nes– is attested in Greek as néomai, but in this case it means simply ‘return’, not ‘return to light and life’. One derivative of néomai is nóstos ’return, homecoming’—and another is nóos. As Frame also argues, the theme of ‘return to light and life’ is recovered by way of the pervasive interplay between the themes of nóos and nóstos within the overall framework of the Odyssey: the key to the nóstos ‘homecoming’ of Odysseus is his nóos, and the nóstos is endangered whenever the nóos is threatened by lḗthē ‘forgetfulness’, as in the story of the Lotus-Eaters. There are in fact two aspects of nóstos in the Odyssey: one is of course the hero’s return from Troy, and the other, just as important, is his return from Hades. Moreover, the theme of Odysseus’s descent and subsequent nóstos ‘return’ from Hades converges with the solar dynamics of sunset and subsequent sunrise. The movement is from dark to light, from unconsciousness to consciousness, as expressed by nóos” (218–219).
Nagy connects this to the language of the Iliadic chariot race:

 

The sēma of the chariot race in honor of the dead Patroklos is not just a ‘tomb’ that serves as a ‘reminder’ of ‘a man who died a long time ago’. It is also a ‘sign’ that was encoded by the nóos of Nés-tōr ’he who brings about a return’ (cf. Il. 23.305). And the word nóos conveys life after death, not only by virtue of its etymology ‘return to light and life’ but also by virtue of its usage in Homeric diction. (219)
In sum, it seems as if the contextual connections of sēma and nóos reflect not only the etymology of nóos as ‘return to light and life’ but also the etymology of sēma as a cognate of Indic dhyāma ’thought’. The related Indic form dhīyas ’thoughts’ is in fact attested as designating the consciousness of man in awakening and reminding the sun, by sacrifice, to rise, as well as the consciousness of man in being reminded by the rising sun to awaken and sacrifice. This theme is in turn closely linked with Indic concepts of life after death. (220)
In conclusion, Nagy connects the interpretation of to the reading of poetry: “the testimony of Greek poetry about sēma and nóēsis turns out to be a lesson in how to read this poetry: the Greek poem is a sēma that requires the nóēsis of those who hear it” (222).
Beekes, R. S. P. 2010. Etymological dictionary of Greek. Leiden.
Brugmann, K., and B. Delbrück. 1886–1900. Grundriß der vergleichenden Grammatik der indogermanischen Sprachen. Strassburg.
Nagy, G. 1990. “Sēma and Nóēsis: The Hero’s Tomb and the ‘Reading’ of Symbols in Homer and Hesiod.” Chapter 8 of Greek Mythology and Poetics. Ithaca, NY. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Greek_Mythology_and_Poetics.1990.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Megan O’Donald 2015.12.24
Σίγειον (Sígeion)
A. The meaning of this name can be connected with the presence of the tomb of the hero Achilles in the environs of that city. Confirmed by comparative evidence in another part of the Greek-speaking world, the city of Taras (Latin Tarentum, modern Taranto) in Magna Graecia offers a traditional explanation for the naming of the city after a sacred space of Achilles that was called Sígeion by ‘the Trojans’ who once lived there. The morphology of the place name Sígeion is parallel to that of Akhílleion; the root of the form Sígeion, is cognate with the root of the adverb sîga ’silently’ and of its derivatives, including the verb sigân ’be silent’ and the adjective sígēlos ’silent’. The name Sígēlos is even attested as the secret name of a cult hero (see Alciphron Letters 3.22.3).
The observance of reverential silence in passing by the tomb of a cult hero is relevant to the naming of another Aeolian site, Sigíā, which is directly comparable to the naming of the old Aeolian site Sígeion. The site of Sigíā is associated with rocky heights overlooking the Hellespont and with tumuli marking the burial places of cult heroes. Both Sígeion and Sigía refer to heights imagined as markers of sacred places where tombs of heroes are located. As for the actual meaning of these Aeolic place names Sígeion and Sigía, both signal a sacred space of reverential silence. By metonymy, the naming of these heights Sígeion and Sigíā is connected with the practice of observing reverential silence at the tombs of heroes.
Nagy, G. 2012. “Conflicting Claims on Homer.” Chapter 7 of Homer the Preclassic. Berkeley. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Homer_the_Preclassic.2009.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Chad Carver 2015.10.30
B. Sígeion: A site in the Troad near which the tomb of Achilles was said to be located; “Achilles was worshipped as a cult hero at this tomb” (Homer the Preclassic II§44). The root of Sígeion is “cognate with the root of the adverb sīga ’silently’ and of its derivatives, including the verb sigân ’be silent’ and the adjective sígēlos ’silent’ (II§134). According to Nagy, the name of the town has its origins in the ritual silence owed to the sacred spaces of cult heroes; he draws a parallel from a reference in Alciphron Letters 3.22.3 to a cult hero Sígēlos and the custom that ”those who pass by the tomb of the cult hero Sígēlos must observe reverential silence” (II§134). The name Sígeion also parallels that of another Aeolian site, Sigíā, which he connects with the name of one of the old cities in the region, Kolōnai, from the plural of kolōnē, ‘tumulus’ (II§135). Nagy concludes that “both Sígeion and Sigíā refer to heights imagined as markers of sacred places where tombs of heroes are located. As for the actual meaning of these Aeolic place names Sígeion and Sigíā, both signal a sacred space of reverential silence. By metonymy, the naming of these heights Sígeion and Sigíā is connected with the practice of observing reverential silence at the tombs of heroes” (Homer the Preclassic II§136).
Nagy, G. 2012. “Conflicting Claims on Homer.” Chapter 7 of Homer the Preclassic. Berkeley. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Homer_the_Preclassic.2009.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Megan O’Donald 2015.10.30
Τηθὺς (Tēthū́s, tḗthea ‘sea-squirts’, tēthúa ‘lagoons’)
The theonym Tēthū́s is the name of the wife of the cosmic river Ocean and mother of all rivers (Hesiod Theogony 337). It is currently connected either to tḗthē ‘grandmother’ (she and Ocean are mentioned as the gods’s ancestors in Iliad 14.302), a derivation which would be unparalleled within Greek, or to the Homeric hapax tḗthea ‘sea-squirts’ (Iliad 16.747; see Frisk 1960-1972:890; DELG: 1113; Beekes 2010:1225-1226). The latter connection is pursued in Ginevra 2020, on which this entry is based.

Τηθὺς δ’ Ὠκεανῷ ποταμοὺς τέκε δινήεντας,
Νεῖλόν τ’ Ἀλφειόν τε καὶ Ἠριδανὸν βαθυδίνην,
Στρυμόνα Μαίανδρόν τε καὶ Ἴστρον καλλιρέεθρον
Tethys bore to Ocean eddying rivers, the Nile and Alpheius and deep-eddying Eridanus, Strymon and Meander and beautiful-flowing Ister [… the list continues]”
Hesiod Theogony 337-339
ἔρχομαι ὀψομένη πολυφόρβου πείρατα γαίης,
Ὠκεανόν τε θεῶν γένεσιν καὶ μητέρα Τηθύν,
οἵ με σφοῖσι δόμοισιν ἐῢ τρέφον ἠδ’ ἀτίταλλον
“I am going to visit the limits of the all-nurturing earth, and Oceanus, from whom the gods are sprung, and mother Tethys, who lovingly nursed me and cherished me in their halls”
Iliad 14.301-303
Given that bodies of water were conceptually associated with the act of ‘foaming, seething’ (on this topic, see further Potamós), Greek Tēthū́s, as a theonym referring to the sea-goddess par excellence, may reflect the personification of an ancient abstract *ku̯ēth2-ú-h2 ‘foamy-ness, seething-ness’ or, less probably, of a feminine ‘she, the foaming/seething one’, a formation of the inherited -ú-h2 type also attested by Homeric ithū́s ‘direction’ (: ithús ‘straight’) and Vedic Sanskrit tanū́- ‘body’ ([*‘length’] : tanú- ‘long’), on which see further Nussbaum 2014:276. If this were the case, the abstract *ku̯ēth2-ú-h2 ‘foamy-ness, seething-ness’ would have been derived from an adjective *ku̯ēth2-ú- ‘foamy, foaming, seething’, a reflex of the PIE root *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’ attested, for instance, by Vedic Sanskrit kváth-ant- ‘foaming, seething’ and Gothic ƕaþjan* ‘to foam, ἀφρίζειν’; the root is currently reconstructed as *ku̯ath2 (LIV2:374) because of a supposed connection with Latin cāseus ‘cheese’, but this etymology is problematic (Schrijver 1991:251-252) and should be dropped. The unexpected lengthened root grade in the adjective *ku̯ēth2-ú- ‘foamy, foaming, seething’ may be due either to the influence of an otherwise unattested so-called “Narten present” (a lengthened-grade root present) with ablaut *ku̯ḗth2 / ku̯éth2 meaning ‘to foam, to seethe’ (for details supporting this, see Ginevra 2020:102 fn. 7), or to an origin of *ku̯ēth2-ú- as an internal (non-suffixed) derivative with lengthened grade of the weak stem ku̯éth2-u- of an acrostatic -u- abstract (type [C]CóC[C]-u-/[C]CéC[C]-u-) of the same root, namely *ku̯óth2-u- / ku̯éth2-u- ‘(state of) foaming, seething’. The latter derivational type is also attested by Homeric ḗn-i-s ‘of one year, one-year-old (of cows)’ from e-ni- ‘year’ in en-i-autós ‘anniversary, lapse of a year’, for a discussion of which see Darms 1978: 113-116, Perpillou 2004: 17, Le Feuver 2018: 196n20.
A partial phonological and morphological parallel for this reconstruction may be found in the second member of Greek Pro-mētheús, the mythical fire-thief’s name. This formation may be transposed as *°māth2-ḗu̯-, a derivative of PIE *math2 ‘steal’ (Narten 1960: 25 fn. 40; Watkins 1995: 255-256 fn. 3) closely matching the Vedic proper name Māthavá- (*māth2-eu̯-ó) that refers to a king associated with fire (he carries it in his mouth) in Śatapatha Brāhmaṇa 1.4.1 (Gotō 2000: 110). The correspondence would exclusively involve the lengthened grade of the root and Greek -th- as the outcome of PIE *-th2; the suffix of Promēth-eú-s, being of unclear origin (but perhaps paralleld by Vedic Māth-av-á-), is not easily linked to the inherited suffix of Tēth-ū́s (*-ú-h2) .
The analysis of Tēthū́s as the reflex of a derivative of an adjective *ku̯ēth2-ú- ‘foaming, seething’ is supported by the fact that a corresponding Greek adjective *tēth-ú-s ‘foaming’ may indeed underlie the Homeric hapax tḗthea ‘sea-squirts (members of the Ascidiacea family)’ and the Hesychian gloss tēthúa ‘lagoons’.
The former is attested in Iliad 16.747, cited below, and may reflect the substantivization via recessive accent of the neuter plural tēth-é()-a (*ku̯ēth2-éu̯-h2) of an adjective *tēth-ú-s ‘foaming, seething’; for the same substantivization type, see also brákh-e()-a ‘shallow water’ from brakh-ú-s ‘short’. Greek *tēth-ú-s may in turn have been the expected outcome of *ku̯ēth2-ú- ‘foaming, seething’, possibly referring to these animals’s habit of violently expelling water from their orifices in specific situations – compare their English name sea-squirt. The synonymous variant tḗthua ‘sea-squirts’ attested in the passage by Aristotle below may correspondingly be the collective plural of *tḗthu ‘sea-squirt’, a noun reflecting the substantivization via recessive accent of the neuter singular *tēth-ú of the same adjective *tēth-ú-s ‘foaming, seething’. The late -s- neuter tē̂th-os is instead a backformation from the neuter plural tḗth-e-a, as if from *ku̯ēth2-es-h2 (see already LSJ, s.v.).

εἰ δή που καὶ πόντῳ ἐν ἰχθυόεντι γένοιτο,
πολλοὺς ἂν κορέσειεν ἀνὴρ ὅδε τήθεα διφῶν
“If he were in the teeming deep, this man would satisfy many by seeking for tḗthea
Iliad 16.746-747
Τὰ δὲ τήθυα μικρὸν τῶν φυτῶν διαφέρει τὴν φύσιν, ὅμως δὲ ζωτικώτερα τῶν 
σπόγγων· οὗτοι γὰρ πάμπαν ἔχουσι φυτοῦ δύναμιν.
“The tḗthua differ very little in their nature from plants, but they are more akin to animals than the Sponges are, which are completely plants.”
Aristotle Parts of Animals 4.681
The last formation relevant here is Greek tēthú* ‘lagoon at the mouth of a river’, attested by the Hesychian gloss  τηθύα· τενάγη, ἃ προχέουσιν οἱ ποταμοί “lagoons, which the rivers pour forth; also a kind of oysters”. The neuter noun tēthú* may be analyzed as the substantivization via ellipsis of the adjective *tēthús reflecting *ku̯ēth2-ú-, possibly originating in a phraseological collocation with the neuter ténagos ‘lagoon’, that is *tēthú ténagos “foamy lagoon”. The semantic shift from ‘foaming, seething’ to ‘lagoon at the mouth of a river’ may be due to the association with rivers, which are generally associated with foaming and seething; see further Potamós.
These parallels thus seem to support the analysis of the theonym Tēthū́s as the reflex of an abstract *ku̯ēth2-ú-h2 ‘foamy-ness, seething-ness’ derived from an adjective *ku̯ēth2-ú- ‘foamy, foaming, seething’ indirectly attested by the substantivizations tḗthea ‘sea-squirts’ and tēthúa ‘lagoons’.
[Translations are adapted from the Loeb Classical Library.]
Beekes, R. 2010. Etymological Dictionary of Greek. Leiden and Boston.
Darms, G. 1978. Schwäher und Schwäger, Hahn und Huhn. Die Vr ̥ddhi-Ableitung im Germanischen. München.
DELG = P. Chantraine. 1968-1980. Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque. Paris.
Frisk, H. 1960-1972. Griechisches Etymologisches Wörterbuch. Heidelberg.
Ginevra, R. 2020. “Foamy Rivers and the Wife of the Ocean: Greek ποταμός ‘river’, Τηθῡ́ς ‘mother of all rivers’, and Proto‑Indo‑European *ku̯eth2 ‘foam, seethe’.” In Papers on Ancient Greek Linguistics. Proceedings of the Ninth International Colloquium on Ancient Greek Linguistics (ICAGL 9), 30 August – 1 September 2018, Helsinki, eds. M. Leiwo, M. Vierros, and S. Dahlgren, 99-110. Helsinki.
Gotō, T. 2000. “‘Purūravas und Urvaśī’ aus dem neuentdecktem Vādhūla-Anvākhyāna (Ed. Ikari).” In Anusantatyai. Festschrift für Johanna Narten, eds. E. Tichy and A. Hintze, 79-110. Dettelbach.
Le Feuvre, C. 2018. “αὖτις δὲ περιπλομένου ἐνιαυτοῦ (Hesiod Op. 386): On the Formation of ἐνιαυτός.” In Vina Diem Celebrent. Studies in Linguistics and Philology in Honor of Brent Vine, eds. D. Gunkel, S. W. Jamison, A. O. Mercado, and K. Yoshida, 191-201. Ann Arbor and New York.
LIV2 = H. Rix, ed. 2001. Lexikon der indogermanischen Verben. Wiesbaden: Reichert.
Narten, J. 1960. Das vedische Verbum math. Indo-Iranian Journal 4.2-3:121-135.
Nussbaum, A. J. 2014. “Feminine, abstract, collective, neuter plural: some remarks on each (expanded handout).” In Studies on the Collective and Feminine in Indo-European from a Diachronic and Typological Perspective, eds. S. Neri and R. Schuhmann, 273-306. Leiden.
Perpillou, J.-L. 2004. “Noms d’animaux.” In Essais de lexicographie en grec ancien, ed. J.-L. Perpillou, 1-22. Louvain.
Schrijver, P. 1991. The reflexes of the Proto-Indo-European laryngeals in Latin. Amsterdam and Atlanta.
Watkins, C. 1995. How to Kill a Dragon: Aspects of Indo-European Poetics. New York and Oxford.
 
Riccardo Ginevra, 2022.10.25
ὕβρις (húbris)
The etymology of húbris is uncertain but deserves attention in view of the cultural importance of the concept. In Homer, húbris is attested in contexts of violence and excess. In particular, Penelope’s suitors are characterized by húbris, and their húbris is both hupérbios ‘exceedingly violent’ (Odyssey 1.368=4.321, 16.410) and atásthalos, a difficult adjective with clear connotations of excess, conventionally translated as ‘reckless, excessive’ (Odyssey 16.86).
The connection between húbris and atasthalíē ‘recklessness, excess’ is also evidenced in Hesiod, where húbris is again atásthalos (Works and Days 134). In Works and Days, húbris is a feature of both the silver (134) and the bronze generations (146). The bronze generation is also described as óbrimos (δεινόν τε καὶ ὄβριμον ‘terrible and mighty’ (145); see below on a possible etymological connection between húbris and óbrimos).
Αnalyzing Pindar’s Pythian 3, addressed to Hieron the tyrant of Syracuse, Nagy observes that the poet, in praising Hieron’s wealth, also issues an implicit warning about the potential danger of excess and the reversals of fortune that can befall those whose material prosperity falls too heavily on them (Nagy 1994:280281). The lines in question are these:

 

ὄλβος {δ’} οὐκ ἐς μακρὸν ἀνδρῶν ἔρχεται
σάος, πολὺς εὖτ’ ἂν ἐπιβρίσαις ἕπηται

 

Pindar Pythian 3.105–106
The prosperity [ólbos] of humans does not go ahead, safe and sound, for a very long time, when it gets attracted [= verb hépomai] to them [= the humans], with its full weight [ἐπιβρίσαις/epibrísais].

Nagy argues that in this passage ἐπιβρίσαις / epibrísais, derived from the verb epi-brī́thō ‘weigh heavily’, hints at húbris, since “this verb is semantically parallel to the noun húbris, the etymology of which is recapitulated in these quoted words of Pindar concerning material prosperity, ólbos, described as coming down with its full weight upon its owner.”

The etymology in question is as follows: húbris is composed of the prefix hu-/u- (ὑ-/ὐ-) in the sense of epí- (ἐπί-) ‘on, on top of’ and bri-/brī- (βρι-/βρῑ-) as in brī́thō ‘to be laden, heavy, full of’ and briarós ‘heavy, massive, solid, strong’. (Perpillou 1987; Chantraine 1968-1980 (DELG) under ὕβρις ascribes this suggestion to “les étymologistes.”)
The stem brī/bri ‘heavy’ is attested in Greek in two forms. The long-vowel form is evidenced by a retrojected word βρῑ, ascribed to Hesiod: Ἡσιόδου δέ, ὅτι τὸ βριθὺ καὶ βριαρὸν βρῖ λέγει ‘[An example on apocope] from Hesiod is that he says brī for brithú and briarón’ (Hesiod fragment 239 MW via Strabo 8.5.3). The short-vowel variant is attested in Herodian: πᾶσα λέξις ἀπὸ τῆς βρι συλλαβῆς ἀρχομένη διὰ τοῦ ι γράφεται οἷον Βρισηΐς, βρί τὸ μέγα, βριθοσύνη τὸ βάρος, βριαρός ὁ ἰσχυρός, βριάειν αὔξειν καὶ οὐκ ἔχει δίφθογγον ‘Every word beginning with the syllable -bri- is written with -i- and not with a diphthong, for example Brisēḯs, brí ‘great’, brithosúnē ‘weight’, briarós ‘strong’, briáein ‘to increase’.’ (Herodian On Orthography 3.2.428). García Ramón traces both forms, brī and bri, to IE * grh2-i, the long form by laryngeal metathesis: *grih2 < gr̥h2-i-. Among other reflexes of * gr̥h2-i- are Vedic girí- and Avestan gairi– ‘high mountain’, Albanian gur, Armenian kar ‘strength, force.’ In Greek, the stem brī /bri is also found in a denominative brīáō which has a double stative/causative function, both ‘to be heavy/strong’ and ‘to make heavy/strong’, as in Works and Days 5: έα μὲν γὰρ βριάει, έα δὲ βριάοντα χαλέπτει ‘for he [Zeus] easily makes one strong, and easily crushes the one who is strong’. Derivatives built on the same stem include brī́thō ‘to be heavy, weighed down’ and also ‘to outweigh, prevail’, brīthús ‘heavy’, brιarós ‘heavy’. All these forms ultimately belong to the root of barús (βαρύς) < *gr̥h2, which, de Lamberterie suggests, is a verbal root *gerh2 ‘to crush, press with one’s weight’> ‘to be heavy, strong’ (de Lamberterie 1982).
Homeric óbrimos ‘strong, mighty’ may belong to the same group (see Perpillou 1987, de Lamberterie 1990, García Ramón 2009). De Lamberterie discusses further important derivatives, a series of nominal forms in -m-, rare but certainly ancient, such as the denominative brīmámai ‘to scold, threaten’, and adjective brimós (glossed by Hesychius as μέγας, χαλεπός ‘big, heavy’).
A Mycenean personal name pu2-ke-qi-ri, attested in Pylos (PY Ta 711) and Thebes (TH Of 27.3, TH Gp 119.1), also contains an element -bri. This name was interpreted by Lejeune (1965) as Φυγέ-βρις. García Ramón analyzes it as Phugegwrīns (the dative form pu2-ke-qi-ri-ne on TH Gp119.1 confirms that the second member of the compound in an n-stem). On the basis of the Homeric usage brīthús, barús, and óbrimos, García-Ramón argues that the Mycenean Phugegwrīns “reflects a verbal phrase, namely a two-member collocation consisting of a verb ESCAPE and a transferred epithet HEAVY.” The transferred epithet designates spear, misfortune, or enemy/Ares. The name, therefore, can be understood as ‘he who escapes the heavy spear/misfortune/enemy’ (García Ramón 2009:19), this being a characteristic of a successful warrior. García Ramón (2009:14n45) notes that “it is possible that ὕβρις belongs to the same lexical group, if it originally means “pression sur” (Perpillou 1987:197) and if ὑ- actually matches ἐπί.” In support of this etymology, and specifically of the equivalence between prefixes epi– (ἐπί) and hu- (ὑ-), de Lamberterie adduces Iliad 7.343 μὴ ποτ’ ἐπιβρίσῃ πόλεμος Τρώων ‘lest the Trojan attack crushes [us]’ and argues that the etymological meaning of húbris suggested by Perpillou, namely ‘pressure upon’, is part of a coherent phraseology associated with the element bri-. In Homer, brīthús, briáō and óbrimos belong to the epic vocabulary of war in which heaviness is linked to violence and oppression (de Lamberterie 1990:534-541).
In Hesiod, a direct link is made between húbris and the verb barúthō ‘to weigh down’ (which, in turn, is connected to br ī́ thō ‘to be heavy’):

 

ὕβρις γάρ τε κακὴ δειλῷ βροτῷ, οὐδὲ μὲν ἐσθλὸς
ηιδίως φερέμεν δύναται, βαρύθει δε ὑπ’ αὐτῆς

 

Works and Days 214-215
Hubris is bad for a poor mortal, not even an excellent man
can bear it easily, but is weighed down by it.

The sentiment of these Hesiodic lines is nearly equivalent to that expressed in Pindar’s Pythian 3.105–106, discussed by Nagy and quoted at the beginning of this entry (Nagy 1994:280–281). In both cases, the mortal is unable to bear the weight that falls upon him. In Hesiod, this weight is explicitly húbris. In Pindar, the weight is that of excessive prosperity, ólbos, but, as Nagy, suggests, a hint at húbris is contained in the participle ἐπιβρίσαις / epibrísais (derived from epi-brī́thō ‘weigh heavily’), which recapitulates the etymology of húbris (the prefix epi– (ἐπί) corresponds to hu- (ὑ-) and is followed, as in húbris, by the stem bri-).

The etymological connection between húbris and brī́thō/brīarós, then, correlates with the poetic connotations of húbris, which link this word both to violence and to the notion of excess. In support of his analysis of epi-brī́thō in Pythian 3, Nagy observes that “the built-in connotations of húbris in this quoted Pindaric passage [Pythian 3.105-106] are reinforced by the following two parallels (Nagy 1994: 281):

 

τίκτει γὰρ κόρος ὕβριν, ὅταν πολὺς ὄλβος ἕπηται
ἀνθρώποις ὁπόσοις μὴ νόος ἄρτιος ᾖ

 

Solon F 6.3–4 W
For insatiability [kóros] gives birth to hubris when much prosperity [ólbos] gets attracted [= verb hépomai] to men whose intent [nóos] is not fit.
τίκτει τοι κόρος ὕβριν, ὅταν κακῷ ὄλβος ἕπηται
ἀνθρώπῳ καὶ ὅτῳ μὴ νόος ἄρτιος ᾖ

 

Theognis 153–154
Insatiability [kóros] gives birth to hubris when prosperity [ólbos] gets attracted [= verb hépomai] to a man who is base [kakós] and whose intent [nóos] is not fit.
The derivation of húbris from bri-/brī- has to remain uncertain because of the scarcity of evidence for the prefix hu-/u-, whose existencе was advocated by Perpillou (1987). The most likely attestations of the prefix are Cypriot ὔχηρος = ἐπίχειρον ’gratuity’ (ICS 217.5, 15) and ὐ τύχα = ἐπὶ τύχῃ (ICS 266, where u-tu-ka in place of the common i-tu-ka (ἰ(ν) τύχα(ι)) is so interpreted by Χατζηϊωάννου 1971, but may stand for σὺν τύχῃ). Α Cypriot gloss in Hesychius may constitute further evidence, although here the prefix seems to appear in the form eu-, not hu-/u-:

 

εὐτρόσσεσθαι· ἐπιστρέφεσθαι. Πάφιοι (Hesychius, s.v. εὐτρόσσεσθαι).
An alternative etymology, not connected to synchronic contexts of húbris, is proposed by Alexander Nikolaev (2004), who suggests that húbris goes back to an i-stem abstract noun *Hxi̯ó/é(h2)g-ri ‘power’ (transponant), internally derived from *Hxi̯á(h2)gu̯-ro ‘mighty’, which is continued by Greek habrós ‘delicate’, both words being built to the root of Greek h‘youth’, the preform of which Nikolaev reconstructs as *Hxi̯ēh2g u̯-eh2. Nikolaev’s suggestion involves a number of presuppositions, among them the modification of the pre-form of hḗbē from the usual *Hxi̯ēgu̯-eh2 to *Hxi̯ēh2gu̯-eh2 in light of its proposed connection with habrós, which, however, is unclear and semantically difficult. One has further to assume a subsequent loss of h2 by the so-called Wetter-rule (postulating the loss of a laryngeal which follows a vowel and precedes a consonant and a sonorant), which is debatable, and an application of Cowgill’s law (o>u in labial environment) which conflicts with a recently updated formulation of this law (Vine 1999). Semantically, Nikolaev’s theory suggests that an earlier meaning of húbris is ‘strength’ or perhaps ‘strength of youth’, depending on the exact historical semantics of hḗbē.
Although there is no consensus regarding the prehistory of húbris, synchronic semantics of this word in its poetic contexts support the etymology advocated by Perpillou, Nagy, and de Lamberterie. The salience of the connection between húbris and the idea of heaviness/weighing down is demonstrated by Nagy’s analyses of húbris in Pindar, Theognis, and Solon.
Beekes, R. 2010. Etymological Dictionary of Greek (EDG). Leiden Indo-European Etymological Dictionary Series 10.1–2. Leiden.
Björck, G. 1954. “Pour les inscriptions en linéaire B peintes sur les vases.” Eranos 52:120-124
———. “Pour le vocabulaire des tablettes ‘à bennières’ de Knossos.” Eranos 52: 271-275.
Chantraine, P. 1968. Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque (DELG). Paris.
García Ramón, J.L. 2009. “Mycenaean Onomastics, poetic phraseology and Indo-European Comparison: the Man’s Name pu2-ke-qi-ri’.” In Kazuhiko Yoshida and Brent Vine (eds.), East and West. Papers in Indo-European Studies. Conference Kyoto University, 11.–12.07.2007. Bremen. 1–26.
Lamberterie, C. de. 1982. “Poids et Force: Reconstruction d’une racine verbale indo-européenne.” Revue des Études Arméniennes 16:21-55.
———.1990. Les Adjectifs grecs en -ύς: sémantique et comparaison. Louvain-La-Neuve.
Lejeune, M. 1965. “Le ΔΑΜΟΣ dans la société mycénienne.” Revue des Études Grecques 78:1-22.
Masson, O. ed. 1961. Les inscriptions chypriotes syllabiques: Recueil critique et commenté. Paris 1961.
Nagy, G. 1994. Pindar’s Homer: The Lyric Possession of an Epic Past. Baltimore.
Nikolaev, A. 2004 [2005]. “Die Etymologie von altgriechischem ὕβρις.” Glotta 80: 211-230.
Perpillou, J.-L. 1987. “Grec ὑ- pour ἐπι.-: un préfixe oublié?” Revue de Philologie 61:193-204.
Χατζηϊωάννου, ΧΚ. 1971. Ἡ Ἀρχαία Κύπρος εἰς τὰς Ἑλληνικὰς Πηγάς. Leukosia.
Vine, B. 1994. “Greek ὄπεας/ὄπεαρ ‘awl’.” Glotta 72:31-40.
———. 1999. “On ‘Cowgill’s law’ in Greek”, in C. Luschützky-H. Eichner (eds.), Compositiones Indogermanicae in memoriam Jochem Schindler. Prague. 555-600.
Weiss, M. 1994. “Life Everlasting: Latin iūgis ‘everflowing’, Greek ὑγιής ‘healthy’, Gothic ajukdūps ‘eternity’ and Avestan yauuaējī ‘living forever’. Münchener Studien zur Sprachwissenschaft 55: 131-156.
 
Olga Levaniouk 10.01.2018
ὕδρα (Hudra)
Homeric Greek Húdr-ē Attic Húdr-ā is the name of a many-headed monster famously slain by the hero Herakles. It literally means ‘Water-female’, being the reflex of the substantivized feminine of a PIE adjective *udr-ó- ‘of water, aquatic’, a derivative of the PIE noun *u̯ed-ōr- ‘water’ (attested by Greek húdōr and English water, among others). This formal analysis is fairly straightforward and accepted by most scholars; a less obvious question, however, is precisely what kind of female water-creature the Hydra was originally imagined as: a serpentine monster (the shape that is most familiar to us) or a canid.
In its earliest mention in Hesiod’s Theogony the Hydra’s shape is not described at all; on the basis of later sources (the first being Peisander of Rhodes, mid-7th century) and of a number of iconographic representations (the earliest being a Boeotian fibula from c. 700 BCE), however, it may be safely assumed that during the first millennium BCE, the Hydra came to be imagined as a serpentine being with many serpentine heads, prompting an interpretation of the name Húdr-ā as ‘water-snake’ (cf. Neue Pauly, s.v.). This serpentine water-monster may have been another Greek reflex of the IE motif of the [serpent – of the watery depth], on which see further Python.
It is, however, at least possible that, before being conflated with the most obvious adversary of IE mythology—the serpent— the Hydra may have originally been more similar to three of her siblings, who were born, like her, from Typhon and Echidna, namely: the two mythological dogs Kerberos (the hell-hound) and Orth(r)os (guardian of Geryon’s herd), as well as their sister (at least according to Hyginus) Scylla, ‘the sea she-hound’, on which see further Sculla.
An original canine shape for the Hydra is suggested by etymological parallels, since, as long noted (Nagy 1985:123), the Greek formation Húdra is similar (differing only in the gender) or even identical to several terms for ‘otter’ in various IE traditions (including English otter), all of which are substantivized reflexes of the PIE adjective *udr-ó- ‘of water, acquatic’; several of these are even feminine, e.g., Latin lutr-a (with initial l- from lavō ‘wash’ or lupus ‘wolf’; de Vaan 2008:355) or German Otter from Proto-Germanic *utr-ō- (cf. Kroonen 2013:562), and may thus be transposed in PIE as *udr-eh2, exactly like Homeric Greek Húdr-ē. Since otters are so-called Caniformia, i.e. “canid-like” mammals, this etymological connection may point to an original canid-like (rather than serpent-like) shape for the Hydra. This reconstruction finds support in two passages of Euripides’s Herakles cited below, where the murderous monster is referred to as tán / tḗn […] kúna (Lérnas) / húdran “the she-hound (of Lerna) / the Hydra”.

τάν τε μυριόκρανον
πολύφονον κύνα 
ὕδραν ἐξεπύρωσεν
The myriad-headed murderous she-hound of Lerna, the Hydra, he destroyed by fire”
Euripides Herakles 419-421
τήν τ’ ἀμφίκρανον καὶ παλιμβλαστῆ κύνα
ὕδραν φονεύσας
“I killed the she-hound whose many heads on all sides grow back again, the Hydra
Euripides Herakles 1274-1275
Since Lerna was a watery place —a complex of springs, a swamp or a lake (see the ancient sources cited in Neue Pauly, s.v.) —the phrase kúna Lérnas “she-hound of Lerna” used by Euripides to refer to the Hydra may be an archaism (pre-dating the conflation of the Hydra with serpent-like adversaries), a reflex of the same inherited collocation [canid – of water] that is used in several Indo-European traditions as the name of dangerous fantastic beasts, including the Greek one, where this collocation underlies the epithet pontía kúōn “sea she-hound” of Scylla, the Hydra’s half-sister. Just like her half-sibling, the Hydra may thus have originally been a Greek reflex (later provided with serpentine features by influence of the adversary par excellence, the Serpent, on which see Python) of the Indo-European monstrous water-canid that is also attested in the Celtic and Germanic traditions, the Irish Water-Dog and the Norse Fen-Wolf Fenrir. On this canine motif, see further Scylla; on the confusion between serpentine and canid-like monsters in Greek mythological lore, see Nagy 2022.
If correct, these considerations may be relevant for the analysis of the Hydra’s name as well. Just like the Ancient Greek noun húdros ‘water-snake’ was probably substantivized by accent-retraction from the adjective *hudrós ‘of water, aquatic’ of a phrase *hudrós óphis “aquatic serpent”, the name Húdr-ā ‘Water-Female’ may have been substantivized by accent-retraction from the adjective *hydrá ‘of water, aquatic’ of an original phrase *hydrá kýōn “aquatic she-hound”, another Ancient Greek reflex of the inherited phrase [canid – of water] used in several IE texts to refer to a monstrous being. The feminine gender would be relatively expected, since Greek kúōn ‘dog (masculine or feminine)’ is usually feminine when it refers to a ‘hound (dog used for killing)’ (LSJ, s.v.). Even though the formulaic phrase *hudrá kýōn reconstructed above is obviously not attested in any Greek text, it may underlie Euripides’s passages above, both of which peculiarly attest appositional phrases tán / tḗn kúna húdran “the she-hound, the Hydra” that seem to intentionally evoke the same formulaic phrase *húdrá kúōn “acquatic she-hound”, of which Scylla’s epithet pontía kúōn “sea she-hound” may either be an innovative variant (if Greek póntos ‘sea’ is an innovation) or a more archaic one (if Greek póntos is related to Old Norse fen and Old Irish on°, see Scylla).
[Translations of Euripides are adapted from the Loeb Classical Library.]
Kroonen, G. 2013. Etymological Dictionary of Proto-Germanic. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Liddell, H., R. Scott, and H. Jones. 1940. A Greek-English Lexicon. Oxford.
Nagy, G. 2022. “Pausanias 3.25.5–6, on Herakles and Cerberus.” Classical Continuum. https://continuum.fas.harvard.edu/pausanias-3-25-5-6-with-translation-and-comments/ (version: 2022.4.4; last access: 2022.5.7)
Nagy, J. 1985-1986. “Otter, Salmon and Eel in Traditional Gaelic Narrative.” Studia Celtica 20-21.123-144.
Vaan, M. de. 2008. Etymological Dictionary of Latin and the other Italic languages. Leiden.
 
Riccardo Ginevra, 2022.10.25
ὑποκρίνεσθαι (hupokrínesthai)
Nagy argues that the verb hupokrínesthai indicates an interesting connection between something that is seen and its interpretation. Beginning with Calchas’s interpretation of the bird sign in Iliad 2, Nagy shows that the verb hupokrínesthai ‘to respond’ implies a “verbal message that responds to a visual message” (Homer the Classic 1§14). This pertains especially to a seer (theoprópos) who is responding to (hupokrínesthai) a vision or an omen. Nagy supports his point by discussing the performative connotations of hupokrínesthai, arguing that hupokrínesthai gives us the word for actor, hupokritḗs, which is best understood “by juxtaposing it with another theatrical word, théātron ’theater’ ” (1§44). Both are quite clearly performative words, and both have to do with seeing and being seen. The form théātron is “composed of verb-root thea– ‘have a vision’ and noun-suffix –tron, indicating an instrument; thus the whole word can be interpreted etymologically as ‘instrument for having a vision [thea-]’. The etymological implications of these two words, théātron and hupokritḗs, can be interpreted together. The audience of theater, of théātron, which is the instrument for achieving théā, or vision, literally sees a vision of a character, such as the Antigone of Sophocles in the drama that is named after her, and this vision of Antigone can then speak for itself. Moreover, the word for ‘audience’ is theātaí ‘spectators’. Thus the mask-wearing actor who is the visualization of, say, Antigone is a hupokritḗs of the theatrical vision of Antigone and of the whole drama that is the Antigone of Sophocles” (1§44).
Nagy’s argument concludes with the idea that hupokrínesthai indicates an act which the seer performs in response to a visual stimulus. “The responsiveness of hupokrínesthai is a matter of performance … The basic idea of hupokrínesthai, then, is to see the real meaning of what others see and to quote, as it were, what this vision is really telling them” (1§158). Nagy argues that hupokrínesthai is particularly relevant to Homeric poetry because this poetry is, by nature, a piece of performance art: “The performance of Homer as a speaker mirrors the performances of the heroes and gods whose speeches he frames. Homer as the framing narrator mirrors the poetic virtuosity of his framed epic characters, especially Achilles. The responsive mentality of speakers in Homeric song extends ultimately to Homer himself, who becomes re-enacted again and again in the traditions of performance. The responsiveness of Homeric poetry, as conveyed by hupokrínesthai, is parallel to the responsiveness of theatrical poetry, as likewise conveyed by the same word hupokrínesthai. Earlier, I argued for the relevance of theatrical contexts of hupokrinesthai in the sense of ‘act’, as in ‘act the role of a persona’, and of hupokritḗs in the sense of ‘actor’. Now I am arguing that Homer himself is such a ‘persona’ in his own right. In that sense, Homer is the embodiment of theater” (1§158–160).
Nagy also discusses hupokrínesthai in Chapter 2 of Homer the Classic (“Homer the Classic in the Age of Callimachus”) in reference to the Homeric Hymn to Apollo. He shows that hupokrínesthai has a performative connotation in the Homeric Hymn to Apollo which is similar to its performative connotation in the Iliad. Says Nagy, “Now we see that the Homeric Hymn (3) to Apollo makes the theatricality [which is implicit in hupokrínesthai] explicit, at verse 163, by way of the word mimeîsthai ’re-enact’. In earlier work, I have argued that the Delian Maidens of the Homeric Hymn (3) to Apollo are in effect offering to make a mī́mēsis of Homer, that is, to ‘re-enact’ him, and Homer responds by making a mī́mēsis of them” (2§29).
Nagy, G. 2009. “Homer the Classic in the Age of Virgil” and “Homer the Classic in the Age of Callimachus.” Chapters 1 and 2 of Homer the Classic. Washington, DC. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Nagy.Homer_the_Classic.2008.
 
Gregory Nagy, edited by Anna Simas, 2015.11.05
Φορωνεύς (Phorōneús)
Phorōneús (Φορωνεύς) is the name of the first man according to a local Argive tradition, where his figure overlaps with that of Prometheus, Φορωνέα ἐν τῇ γῇ ταύτῃ γενέσθαι πρῶτον […] οὐ γάρ τι ὁμολογοῦσι δοῦναι πῦρ Προμηθέα ἀνθρώποις, ἀλλὰ ἐς Φορωνέα τοῦ πυρὸς μετάγειν ἐθέλουσι τὴν εὕρεσιν “(some say that) Phoroneus was the first man in this land […] for they do not admit that fire was given to mankind by Prometheus, but insist on assigning the discovery of fire to Phoroneus” (Pausanias Description of Greece 2.15.5).
The name Phorōneús reflects a personal name ending in –eús, which in Greek usually occurs beside a thematic stem in –os, for example híppos ‘horse’ beside hippeús ‘horseman’. Not only do names in –ōneús pair with thematic stems in –ōnós, but sometimes they also point to an original n-stem as their derivational basis. For instance, kolōnós ‘hill’ (κολωνός Homeric Hymn 2.272) pairs with Kolōneús (Κολωνεύς, toponym in Inscriptiones Graecae 2.944.48); meledōnós (μελεδωνός) ‘attendant, guardian’ (Herodotus Histories 3.61) pairs with melodōneús (μελεδωνεύς) ‘attendant, guardian’ (Theocritus Idylls 24.106). A man’s name Phorōnós is preserved in the corpus of the Suida (under φ 616): Φορωνεύς· ὄνομα. καὶ Φόρωνος, ὄνομα κύριον “Phorōneús: name. Also Phorōnós, proper name.” Both Phorōneús and Phorōnós belong to the same root as Greek phérō (φέρω) ‘bring’, that is to say, Indo-European *bher– ‘bring, carry’, which underlies verbs for ‘carry, bring’ in several languages, such as Latin ferō, Vedic bhar, Gothic bairan. The etymology of the personal name, together with the role of Phorōneús in the Argive tradition, is a clue at the inherited background of this figure.
If the ‘Argive Prometheus’ Phoroneus is ‘the one who brings (something)’, Prometheus is the ‘fire-bringer’, as evidenced by his epithet pūrphóros (πυρφόρος) in Sophocles’s Oedipus in Colonus 55. In turn, the Vedic counterpart of Prometheus, Mātariśvan, is described both as the ‘fire-robber’ and the ‘fire-bringer’. Indeed, Vedic bhar ‘bring’ (also occurring in a prefixed form, ā́-bhar) often describes Mātariśvan’s achievement: Rigveda 1.93.6a ā́nyáṃ divó mātaríśvā jabhāra “Mātariśvan bore the one here from heaven” (translation Jamison and Brereton 2014).
Just as Phorōneús is both a ‘fire bringer’ and the ‘first Argive man’, the role of ‘fire-bringer’ is assigned to the first inhabitant of a place in other literary traditions. In a north Scandinavian tradition, the Guta Saga, it is Þieluar, Gotland’s first inhabitant, that brought fire on the island for the first time, cf. Gutland hitti fyrsti maþr þann sum Þieluar hit … En þann maþr quam fyrsti eldi a land “Gotland was first discovered by a man named Þieluar … that man, however, was the first that brought fire to the island.”
In conclusion, Phorōneús can be identified as a doppelgänger of the fire-thief. Indeed, like Prometheus in Greek and Mātariśvan in Vedic he is a ‘fire-bringer’. At the same time, the role of Phorōneús as the first inhabitant of Argos parallels that of the Gutnic fire-bringer Þieluar.
Jamison, Stephanie W., and Joel P. Brereton, trans. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. 3 Vols. Oxford.
Massetti, L. (in print). “Another avatar of Mātariśvan?” Proceedings of the 29th UCLA Indo-European Conference, eds. D. Goldstein, S. Jamison, and B. Vine. Bremen.
 
Laura Massetti 2018.08.29
φύλαξ, Φύλακος (Phúlaх and Phúlakos)
The subastantive phúlaх (φύλαξ) means ‘sentinel’ and is first attested in the Greek epics. As convincingly proposed by Kölligan (2016:127–131), it can be traced back to the Indo-European root *bhelH– ‘to utter a sound’, which, among others, underlies Old English bellan ‘to cry out’, Old High German bellan ‘to bark’, and Lithuanian prabìlti ‘to start to talk.’ Greek substantives in –ak– commonly pair with thematic forms and, possibly, thematic verbs in –i̯e/o-. For instance, Greek múlax (μύλαξ) ‘millstone’ exists besides the feminine substantive múlē ‘hand-mill’ (μύλη), which ultimately points of a thematic stem *molo/eh2-, and a present múllō ‘to have sex’ (μύλλω, found in Theocritus 4.58), reflecting *molh2 i̯e/o– with u -vocalism mul– instead of mol– due to the evolution of the group *oli̯– into Greek –ull– (Vine 1999:564–567, 582). In an analogous way, phúlax may pair with a thematic form *phólos and a present in *phol(H)i̯e/o– (from *bholHi̯e/o-), which would have appeared as *phúllō in Greek. Although such a form is unattested, Old Norse beljan ‘to cry out’ may reflect a present *bholH-i̯e/o-.
The phraseological analysis provides support for the proposed etymology. Indeed, sentinels are commonly associated with the idea of ‘emitting a loud sound, giving the alarm’ in Greek.

οὐδὲ μὲν εὕδοντας φυλάκων ἡγήτορας εὗρον,
ἀλλ᾽ ἐγρηγορτὶ σὺν τεύχεσιν εἵατο πάντες.
ὡς δὲ κύνες περὶ μῆλα δυσωρήσωνται ἐν αὐλῇ
θηρὸς ἀκούσαντες κρατερόφρονος, ὅς τε καθ᾽ ὕλην
ἔρχηται δι᾽ ὄρεσφι· πολὺς δ᾽ ὀρυμαγδὸς ἐπ᾽ αὐτῷ
ἀνδρῶν ἠδὲ κυνῶν, ἀπό τέ σφισιν ὕπνος ὄλωλεν·
ὣς τῶν νήδυμος ὕπνος ἀπὸ βλεφάροιιν ὀλώλει
νύκτα φυλασσομένοισι κακήν · […]
‘They found the leaders of the sentinels not asleep, but all were sitting awake with their weapons. And just as dogs keep painful watch about sheep in a fold, when they hear the wild beast, stout of heart, that comes through the wood among the hills, and a great din arises about him of men and dogs, and from them sleep perishes; so from their eyelids did sweet sleep perish, as they kept watch through the evil night …’
(Iliad 10.181–186)

The parallel between barking dogs and sentinels is also found in Plato: In the Republic (375a, 375e), Plato explicitly compares the sentinels of the ideal state, phúlakes, to young dogs (skúlakes, kúnes).

Finally, it is significant that Delphic hero Phúlakos is connected to the idea of great clamor of war. Herodotus (8.37.3) tells us that when the Persians were attacking the temple of Athena Pronaia at Delphi (480BCE) two rocks broke off from Parnassus and came rushing [[crushing?]] among them, while ‘a shout and a cry of triumph’ (βοή τε καὶ ἀλαλαγμός) came from the temple. According to the survivors, however, two local heroes, Phúlakos and Autónoos, had pursued the barbarians. The clamor heard from the temple could thus be connected with the alarm given by Phúlakos and Autónoos, the sentinels par excellence.
In conclusion, Greek phúlax (and Phúlakos) can be rightly identified as the ‘the one who gives the alarm.’ The phraseological analysis supports the etymological connection between Greek phúlax and the Indo-European root *bhelH– ‘to utter a sound.’
Kölligan, D. 2016. “Trois noms grecs en -ak-: πῖδαξ, λῦμαξ, φύλαξ.” In: A. Blanc, and D. Petit (eds.): Nouveaux acquis sur la formation des noms en grec ancien : actes du colloque international, Université de Rouen, ERIAC, 17-18 octobre 2013, 117–133. Louvain: Peeters.
Vine, B. 1999. “On ‘Cowgill’s Law’ in Greek.” In H. Eichner, H. C. Luschützky (eds.): Compositiones Indogermanicae in Memoriam Jochem Schindler, 555-600. Praha: Enigma.
 
Laura Massetti 2021.04.18
Χείρων, Χίρων, Χέρρων (Kheirōn)
Chiron, the son of the nymph Philyra and of Cronus (Pherecydes fr. 2.3 M), is described in the epics as ‘the most righteous among the Centaurs’ (δικαιότατος Κενταύρων, Iliad 11.832) and as ‘having friendly thoughts’ (φίλα φρονέων, Iliad 4.219). His name is attested in three variants: Kheirōn (Χείρων) is the most recurrent in the literary sources (from Homer onward, with a few exceptions, such as Pindar, Euripides fr. 14.13 P, Acusilaus fr. 16.2 DK); Khīrōn (Χίρων) is often attested in the documentary sources (for example, Attic vase paintings of the fifth century BCE and one inscription from Thera in the sixth century BCE); Kherrōn (Χέρρων) occurs only in Alcaeus (fr. 42.9 V).
If Kheirōn (Χείρων) is the original form, the name may be related to Greek kheir (χείρ) ‘hand’ (Kretschmer 1919:58–62), meaning ‘the one who has a special hand’. The form Kherrōn (Χέρρων), if genuine and not the result of a secondary ‘aeolicization’, supports this assumption (compare χέρρες ‘hands’ Sappho fr. 90[1].2 V).
If Khīrōn is the primary form, the etymology is unclear. In this scenario, the forms Kheirōn and Kherrōn should both be explained as secondary formations under the influence of folk etymologies linking Chiron’s name to kheir ‘hand’ (Wachter 2001:263–264).
Without any doubt, ancient literary sources connected Chiron with the ‘healing hand’ and the ‘healing practice’ (kheirourgiā). Indeed, Chiron mentors a number of young heroes connected with both hunting and healing, such as Jason, Aristaeus, Asclepius, and Achilles. Specifically, Pindar says that Chiron ‘taught’ his students ‘the gentle-handed province of medicines’ (Χίρων … τὸν φαρμάκων δίδαξε μαλακόχειρα νόμον, Pindar Nemean 3.53–55). Additionally, the name of Jason (Ἰάσων), one of Chiron’s pupils, actually means ‘healer’ (compare Greek ἰάομαι ‘to treat’, ἰατήρ ‘physician’).
Chiron’s distinctive features are comparable to those of other divine figures who have a healing ‘hand’ (Greek kheir, Vedic hástaḥ, Hittite keššar, from the common Indo-European root *ghes-, enlarged with different suffixes) in other Indo-European traditions, namely the Vedic god Rudra, who has a ‘merciful’ (mr̥ḷayā́kuḥ, R̥gveda 2.33.7) or ‘healing hand’ (bheṣajaḥ … hástaḥ, R̥gveda 2.33.7), and the Hittite ‘Sun-god of the hand’ (Hittite kiššeraš DUTU-uš) invoked in the ritual of the Catalogue des Textes Hittites 402.
The three figures share an association with the activity and equipment of the hunt, that is, of the bow, arrows, and hounds. In the epics, Chiron, who is an experienced hunter, is mentioned in connection with remedies applied to arrow wounds (Iliad 4.217–219); however, he is killed by one of Heracles’ arrows (Diodorus Siculus Library 4.12.8, Hyginus Astronomica 2.38.1). Afterwards, he is transformed either into the constellation Sagittarius (‘the arrow shooter’ Lucan Pharsalia 6.393–394) or into the constellation Centaurus (Hyginus Astronomica 2.38.1). The Vedic god Rudra controls remedies while also causing diseases and death with his arrows. He is the god ‘who possesses good arrow’ (suviṣúḥ, R̥gveda 5.42.11) and ‘good bow’ (sudhánvā, R̥gveda 5.42.11), but he is also ‘men-smiting’ (nr̥hán-, R̥gveda 4.3.6). Additionally, he protects hounds, masters of hounds, and hunters (Vājasaneyi Saṃhitā 16.27–28). In the Hittite Ritual of Allī against Bewitching (Catalogue des Textes Hittites 402), the Hittite kiššeraš DUTU-uš (‘Sun-god of the hand’) is opposed to a hunter clay-figure, who has hounds, arrows, and a bow. In the ritual, the hunter and his arrows represent, like Rudra’s arrows, what the ‘Sun-god of the hand’ has to remove (Mouton 2010).
Chiron and Rudra have further traits in common. They are compared to or called ‘wild beasts’ (Greek φήρ; Vedic mr̥gáṃ ná bhīmám ‘like a fearful beast’, R̥gveda 2.33.11). Furthermore, they are inhabitants of mountains par excellence. Chiron dwells on Mount Pelion in Thessaly (Χείρων ἵν’ οἰκεῖ σεμνὰ Πηλίου βάθρα ‘where Chiron lives, the holy glens of Pelion’ Euripides Iphigenia at Aulis 705), and, like other Centaurs, he is a ‘mountain dweller’ (Greek oreiskōios, of all the Centaurs, Iliad 1.268). Likewise, Rudra is called ‘mountain dweller’ (giriśayá-, Vājasaneyi Saṃhitā 16.29). Finally, Chiron and Rudra are connected with young warriors: Chiron rears several young heroes and is a wise friend of heroes and gods. He bestows upon Peleus his ‘ash spear for the smiting of men’ (μελίην φόνον ἔμμεναι ἡρώεσσιν, Iliad 16.143, 19.390), suggests that he take Thetis as his bride by force ([Apollodorus] Library 3.168), and predicts to Apollo that he will carry away the nymph Cyrene after their consensual union (Pindar Pythian 9). In the R̥gveda, Rudra is the ‘father of the Maruts’ (pitar marutām, R̥gveda 2.33.1), a group of atmospheric deities portrayed as young warriors and young bride wooers, which vaguely recalls Chiron’s role with regard to young and unmarried heroes.
In conclusion, the folk etymological association between Chiron’s name and the ‘healing hand’ might itself be based on a set of associations shared by Greek and two cognate languages, Vedic and Anatolian. Here, (semi-)divine figures dwelling in wild and liminal realms are connected to young age groups, hunting activity, and the healing of arrow wounds, which frequently occur on the occasion of hunting incidents and group fights. Therefore, Chiron, the Greek ‘Mr. (Healing) Hand’, might be interpreted as a continuation of a more ancient ‘Mr. (Healing) Hand’.
Kretschmer, P. 1919. “Mythische Namen.” Glotta 10: 38–62.
Massetti, L. In preparation. “Mr. Hand: On Gk. Χείρων, Rudrá– ‘of healing hand’ and Hitt. kiššeraš DUTU-uš.”
Wachter, R. 2001. Non-Attic Greek Vase Inscriptions. Oxford.
 
Laura Massetti 2018.05.29
Ὠκεανός (Ōkeanós)
Ōkeanós, often translated as ‘Ocean’, is the name of a cosmic potamós ‘river’ (Iliad 18.607, Odyssey 11.639) of Ancient Greek mythology, from whom all rivers and streams are said to flow (Iliad 21.195-197). A Titan son of Gaia ‘Earth’ and Ouranos ‘Sky’, according to Hesiod (Theogony 337) Okeanos was the father of all deified Potamoí ‘Rivers’ (on which see further Potamós), whom he begot together with the female Titan Tethys (on which see further Tēthū́s), his sister and spouse. The following are some of Okeanos’s earliest features in epic diction (as summarized in Nagy 1990:236-239) that are most relevant here: he marks the boundaries of Earth (Iliad 14.301-302); the Sun rises from him (Iliad 7.421-423; Odyssey 19.433-434) and falls into him at sunset (Iliad 8.485); correspondingly, Okeanos must surround the Earth, as also shown by the fact that the scenes of everyday life on the Shield of Achilles are framed as a whole by a depiction of Okeanos along the shield’s rim (Iliad 18.607-608). As pointed out by Nagy (1990:237), several of Okeanos’s features have correspondences in those of his and Tethys’s son Eridanos, on which see Ēridanós.
An Indo-European etymology for Ōkeanós is considered unlikely by Robert Beekes (2010:1677, s.v. Ὠκεανός), who states that “since the idea of a world river is not of IE origin, the word must be a loan”, and traces it back to “a Pre-Greek form *ūkān”: however, on the one hand, the latter reconstruction finds no parallels in any ancient or modern languages known to us; on the other hand, the belief that a generic body of water encircles the entire Earth may well be of Indo-Europeanm origin, as it is actually attested not only in the earliest Greek tradition (as argued by Nagy), but also (at least) in the Indic and Germanic ones (cf., e.g., West 2007:349 —who is, however, skeptical). Indeed, the role of Okeanos as “encircler of the Earth” has led Michael Janda (2005:231ff; 2010:57ff) to argue in favor of an IE etymology for Ancient Greek Ōkeanós that had been first formulated explicitly by Adalbert Kuhn (1860:240; building on previous proposals by Theodor Benfey and Adolphe Pictet—see Janda 2005:231-233 for a summary), namely as the reflex of an inherited formation *ō-ḱei̯m̥h1no– ‘lying (up)on, near’, a middle participle stem of the verbal root *ḱei̯- ‘to lie, to be lying’ (Ancient Greek keî-mai ‘lie’, Vedic Sanskrit śáy-e ‘lie’) prefixed with the particle *ō- ‘(upo)on, near’ (Vedic preverb ā́- ‘near, near to, towards’), whose Vedic Sanskrit reflex ā-śáyāna- ‘lying (up)on, near’ is indeed attested several times with the serpent Vr̥tra (vr̥trá-) as referent and a term for body of water as location, either in the locative case (as sirā́su ‘in/on the streams’) or in the accusative case (as síndhum ‘towards the river’ and apá ‘towards the waters’):

tuváṁ vr̥trám āśáyānaṁ sirā́su / mahó vájreṇa siṣvapo varā́hum
RV 1.121.11cd
“You put Vr̥tra to sleep powerfully with your mace, as he was lying upon the streams, (and you put to sleep) the boar [=Śuṣṇa?]”

índro mahā́ṁ síndhum āśáyānam / māyāvínaṁ vr̥trám asphuran níḥ

RV 2.11.9 ab
“Indra kicked away wily Vr̥tra, lying upon the great river.”

áhim ohānám apá āśáyānam / prá māyā́bhir māyínaṁ sakṣad índraḥ

RV 5.30.6cd
The serpent vaunting himself, lying on the waters – Indra will overcome the tricky one with tricks.”
In the light of these correspondences, Janda thus traces Okeanos’s character and name back to those of an inherited figure, the IE cosmic serpent *ōḱei̯m̥h1no- ‘lying upon, near’ the waters that encircle the Earth (on which see further Pýthōn). Given that the expected Ancient Greek reflex of an inherited participle *ōḱei̯m̥h1no- ‘lying (up)on, near’ would actually be something like †Ōkeemeno- or †Ōkeimēno- (the sequence *m̥h1 may have both Ancient Greek eme and as outcomes), Janda needs to assume a (relatively unproblematic) early deletion of the laryngeal in compound form (by the so-called “neognós Rule”), which would indeed have resulted in *ōḱei̯m̥no- and its straightforward Ancient Greek outcome Ōkeanós; within this account, the Vedic Sanskrit reflex ā-śáyāna- must have undergone restoration of the suffix at some point (either as earlier *-m̥h1no- or Vedic -āna-).
As discussed by Janda (2005:235-236), this proposal is supported by famous depictions of Okeanos himself with serpentine features in both iconographic sources (cf. LIMC 7/2, 22) and poetic texts, such as Hesiod’s Theogony, where Okeanos is described as heiligménos ‘coiling, winding, whirling’, a form of the verb elíssō ‘coil, wind, roll’, elsewhere often used with snakes and serpents as referents:

Ōkeanoîo kéras […]· / ennéa mèn perì gên te kaì euréa n ō̂ ta thalássēs
Dínēis arguréēis heiligménos eis hála píptei

Hesiod Theogony 789-792
“a branch of Ocean […]. For nine-fold around the earth and the broad back of the sea
he whirls in silver eddies and falls into the sea”

smerdaléon dè dédorken elissómenos perì kheiē̂

Iliad 22.95
“and terribly he (a serpent) glares as he coils about inside his lair”
If one accepts Janda’s proposal that Okeanos originated as a Greek reflex of the IE cosmic serpent *ōḱei̯m̥h1no- ‘lying (up)on, near’ the waters, a further interesting etymological and thematic parallel, supporting Janda’s analysis, may be found in Sanskrit epic. Within this tradition, one of the two names of the great cosmic serpent (beside Ananta-) is Sanskrit Śeṣa-, which, as briefly suggested during a CIGE meeting by Olga Levaniouk, may easily traced back to the IE verbal root *ḱei̯- ‘lie, be lying’ (Sanskrit śe-/śay-), matching his characterization as a giant serpent who lies around the earth and the encircling waters:

bibharti devīṃ śirasā mahīm imāṃ samudranemiṃ parigṛhya sarvataḥ
Mahābhārata 1.32.22.2
“(Śeṣa) carries the Goddess Earth on his head, encompassing all around the circumference of the oceans

śeṣo ‘si nāgottama dharmadevo mahīm imāṃ dhārayase yad ekaḥ / anantabhogaḥ parigṛhya sarvāṃ yathāham evaṃ balabhid yathā vā

Mahābhārata 1.32.23
“Thou art Śeṣa, greatest of Snakes, thou art the God of Law, for thou alone lendest support to this earth, encircling her entire with endless coils, not less than I support her, or the Cleaver of Vala”

catuḥsamudraparyantāṃ merumandarabhūṣaṇām / śeṣo bhūtvāham evaitāṃ dhārayāmi vasuṃdharām

Mahābhārata 3.187.10
as Śeṣa I support this treasure-filled earth that is girt by the four oceans and adorned with the Meru and Mandara”
As for the derivational process leading to Sanskrit Śeṣa-, I analyze the latter as either a more recent deverbal formation (e.g., based on the aorist subjunctive stem śéṣa- attested in RV 1.174.4a) or as a reflex of earlier śeṣá-, regular outcome of an inherited formation of the “pexus type” (Höfler 2017:58ff) *ḱei̯-s-ó- ‘who has (the property of) lying around’, a possessive derivative of an earlier -s- abstract *ḱéi̯-es- ‘(the property of) lying around’. An exact parallel for this analysis would be the Vedic noun jeṣá- ‘winning, gaining’ (RV. 1.100.11; 6.44.18), which may be analyzed (see Höfler 2017:469 for the details) either as a recent deverbal formation (based on the aorist subjunctive stem jéṣa-) or as the substantivized reflex of an inherited “pexus type” *gei̯-s-ó- ‘who has (the property of) winning, gaining’, a possessive derivative of an -s- abstract *géi̯-es- ‘(the property of) winning, gaining’ (attested by the Vedic infinitive jiṣé in RV 1.111.4; 1.112.12).
If it is indeed a reflex of the IE cosmic serpent *ō-ḱei̯m̥h1no- ‘lying (up)on, near’ the waters that encircle the Earth, the character and name of Okeanos may thus have a close etymological and thematic parallel in the character and name of the cosmic serpent Śeṣa of Sanskrit epic, if the latter is indeed a reflex of *ḱei̯-s-ó- ‘who has (the property of) lying around’.
On the names of Okeanos’s spouse and children, see further Tēthū́s and Potamós respectively; on other Greek reflexes of the IE cosmic serpent associated with water, see further Pýthōn.
Translations
Translations of Classical sources are adapted from the Loeb Classical Library. Translations of the RV are adapted from:
Jamison, Stephanie W. & Joel P. Brereton. 2014. The Rigveda. The Earliest Religious Poetry of India. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.
References
Beekes, R. 2010. Etymological Dictionary of Greek. Leiden & Boston: Brill.
Höfler, S. 2017. Der Stier, der Stärke hat. Possessive Adjektive und ihre Substantivierung im Indogermanischen. Unpublished PhD thesis, University of Vienna.
Janda, M. 2005. Elysion. Entstehung und Entwicklung der griechischen Religion. Innsbruck: Institut für Sprachen und Literaturen der Universität Innsbruck.
Janda, M. 2010. Die Musik nach dem Chaos. Der Schöpfungsmythos der europäischen Vorzeit. Innsbruck: Institut für Sprachwissenschaft der Universität Innsbruck.
Kuhn, A. 1860. ὠκεανός. Zeitschrift für vergleichende Sprachforschung auf dem Gebiet des Deutschen, Griechischen und Lateinischen 9.240
LIMC = 1981–1999. Lexicon iconographicum mythologiae classicae. Zürich und München: Artemis und Winkler.
Nagy, G. 1991. Greek Mythology and Poetics. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.
West, M. 2007. Indo-European Poetry and Myth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 
Riccardo Ginevra 2022.10.25